The Theological Ontology of Leontius of Byzantium and the Circumscribability Argument in the Iconophile Polemics

Бесплатный доступ

The theological contribution of Leontius of Byzantium played a crucial role in adapting the notions of substance and hypostasis from their original Trinitarian to a Christological context. The Leontian concepts, such as enhypostasized substance, distinction between the principle of substance and mode of existence, as well as “relational” ontology of reversed unions and distinctions at the levels of substances and hypostases was adopted by Maximus the Confessor and John of Damascus in their polemical application of Neo-Chalcedonian Christology, as well as the by the Iconophiles of the Second Iconoclasm in support of the circumscribability of Christ.

Еще

Leontius of Byzantium, Maximus the Confessor, John of Damascus, Theodore the Studite, Patriarch Nicephorus of Constantinople, hypostasis, substance, properties, circumscribability

Короткий адрес: https://sciup.org/147237645

IDR: 147237645   |   DOI: 10.25205/1995-4328-2022-16-2-462-481

Текст научной статьи The Theological Ontology of Leontius of Byzantium and the Circumscribability Argument in the Iconophile Polemics

* This study was supported by the Russian Foundation for Basic Research, project No. 19011-00778, “Leontius of Byzantium and Patristics.” Данное исследование выполнено при финансовой поддержке РФФИ в рамках научного проекта №19-011-00778 «Леонтий Византийский и патристическая традиция».

Hypostasis is a traditional theological category elaborated during the Trinitarian Controversy of the fourth century for distinguishing numerically different Persons in the Holy Trinity united in their common substance, and essentially understood as individualized divine substance with distinguishing personal proper-ties.1 However, in the Christological controversies of the sixth century, this notion

of hypostasis as the principle of individuation proved to be insufficient for the proponents of the Council of Chalcedon, since their Miaphysite or Nestorian adversaries could use it to justify their doctrine of one composite nature of Christ, or conversely, of two hypostases of Christ corresponding to his human and divine natures.2 In a new paradigm, the theological concepts of substance and hypostasis of the Cappadocians3 were rethought based on the Aristotelian and Neoplatonic philosophical framework.4 Maximus the Confessor thus described this paradigmatic shift in the application of the term “hypostasis”: “According to the philosophers, hypostasis is substance with properties, while according to the Fathers, it is each individual man, personally distinguished from other human be-ings,”5 indicating the need for a different context and conceptual apparatus needed for the Christological application of the term.

Several polemical treatises of Leontius of Byzantium (ca. 485–ca. 543) against the Miaphysite and Nestorian Christological positions played a crucial role in adapting the notions of substance and hypostasis from their Trinitarian meaning for solving Christological problems and elaborating a conceptual framework for the notions of substance, hypostasis, and properties in order to clarify the Chal-cedonian formula “two natures in one hypostasis.”

One of the most important contributions of Leontius of Byzantium is further elaboration of the concept of “enhypostasized” substance which has its being in a hypostasis other than its own, used for safeguarding the Chalcedonian doctrine on the unconfused union of two natures in one Christ Incarnated.6 The history of this concept, its development by Leontius of Byzantium, and its reception in the Christological discussions has been a subject of numerous studies.7 Maximus the Confessor (ca. 580–662) and John of Damascus (ca. 676–before 754) were important authors in the reception, development, and transmission of this and other concepts by Leontius of Byzantium.8

Thus, Maximus followed the Leontian distinction of “hypostasis” and “enhy-postasized,” and elaborated a consistent system of terminology, applicable equally well to the intra-Trinitarian relations of hypostases and Christological relations of natures.9 He consolidated the identity of Christ Incarnated as the Word of God – the second hypostasis of the Trinity timelessly born from the Father and born from the Mother in time – by treating the property of Sonship as a mode of existence, since in both generations the hypostasis of the Word actualized divine and human natures without altering their logoi in their new mode of existence10 and appropriated the properties of both natures as His own.

Maximus adopted the Leontian distinction of the principle of substance (or being—λόγος τῆς οὐσίας or λόγος τοῦ εἶναι) and mode of existence (τρόπος τῆς ὑπάρξεως or τοῦ πῶς εἶναι τρόπος) introduced in the context of the Christological debates.11 According to Maximus, in the Incarnation, the Word replaced the male seed in conception and thereby acquired the human mode of existence entailing mortality, and in this new tropos preserving the intact logoi of His both natures and unity of hypostasis.12 This view was based on Aristotle’s suggestion that the male semen gives form and the principle of movement to the matter provided by the female.13 The soul acquired with the male seed, gradually reveals itself in actuality with the formation of each relevant organ as a form participating in the formation of the body.14 In the context of the Incarnation, Christ’s conception was considered to be seedless, and his human soul did not join his body through male semen, but through the activity of the Holy Spirit. Maximus the Confessor thus explains the phrase of the Nicene-Constantinopolitan Creed, “and was incarnate by the Holy Spirit and the Virgin Mary”: “Some among the saints say that the soul is sown by the Holy Spirit in the manner of a man’s parent, and the flesh is formed from the virginal blood.”15

According to Maximus, in the Incarnation, the divine nature and human nature did not change their principle of being, but aquired a new mode of existence in the composite hypostasis of Christ, when the Word of God became the individuating and structuring principle in the formation of Christ’s body in the virginal womb. Thus, the bodily and facial features, complexion, height and other visible features of Christ perceived by the senses could properly be understood as those shaped by and belonging to the Word of God. Moreover, the divinity in Christ is comprehended not only through intellection – the very face of God on Mount Tabor reveals the hiddenness of His divinity, according to Maximus’ treatment of the Transfiguration.16

John of Damascus sometimes employed the Leontian idea in the form moderated by Maximus,17 as was the case with the concept of the divine hypostasis of the Word which preserved its unchangeable principle of divine nature but willed to exist in another mode in the Incarnation by replacing the human seed which naturally provides hypostasis to humans, and existing in the human tropos.18 On other occasions, John of Damascus used Leontius directly, such as his close paraphrase of a Leontian passage against the Myaphysites that number does not introduce division but merely indicates a totality or quantity, and thus rather unites than divides, where John of Damascus reproduced not only the argument and its wording, but also the examples which Leontius provided for illustrating his point.19

Leontius of Byzantium's apology of the Chalcedonian Christology of two natures and one hypostasis was based on the ontological perception of the ratio : the Word was united to humanity the same way as a human soul is united to its body. This analogy had serious limitations; one of them was that multiple compounds of soul-body constitute the human species, whereas there is only one divinehuman compound Christ without a corresponding species20 and Leontius was aware of that.21 Moreover, Leontius pushed the analogy so far as to claim that both body and soul were perfect in themselves and their “imperfection” could only be applied to the composite of the whole in which they existed;22 even en-soulment occurred as a supernatural act of God,23 and they were regarded as distinct natures as far as their principles of substance are concerned. However, in conjuction, they are still perceived as one human species, and have a common definition, which could easily give way to Miaphysite abuse of the analogy, using it precisely for their claim of one composite nature of Christ.24

Maximus, and John of Damascus who followed him, overcame the limitations of the analogy taken in a strict sense by assigning one of the two definitions of hypostasis mentioned in Leontius of Byzantium25 to the natural union of hypostases in the species, and the other one exclusively to the composite supernatural union which does not emerge from natural procreation of individuals in the spe-cies.26 By integrating the Leontian distinction of hypostasis into Neo-chalcedonian Christology, they emphasized the extraordinary nature of the hypostatical actualization of Christ indicating the unique composite hypostasis and not a member of the species or composite nature.27

The concept of enhypostaton in Leontius of Byzantium was not an isolated idea; his apologetic drive was underlined by a carefully designed philosophical system. In order to expose the mistake of two theological camps, Leontius created his Christological framework which would safeguard both the union of natures in single subject Christ, and their distinction of natures. Leontius defines substance as the universal determination in which beings receive the definition of their nature. Accordingly, hypostasis is the individualizing determination of the unions and distinctions of beings. Thus, according to Leontius, nature provides:

the definition of being (τὸν τοῦ εἶναι λόγον), but hypostasis also [the definition] of be-ing-by-oneself (τὸν τοῦ καθ᾽ ἑαυτὸν εἶναι), and the former comprises the definition of species, while the latter indicates the individual. And the former indicates the character of a universal thing, while the latter distinguishes the particular from the general.28

In this passage, Leontius of Byzantium treated both “substance” and “hypostasis” as universal definitions of unions and distinctions in beings, and as definitional opposites to one another: if the hypostasis is put in distinction, the substance must be put in the opposite relation, that is, union. For this conceptual framework, Leontius introduced the twofold relations of beings:

All beings are joined to each other by universal commonalities (ταῖς καθόλου κοινότησι) and are distinguished from each other by specific differences (εἰδοποιοῖς διαφοραῖς)… And the definition of these unions and distinctions is twofold (διττὸς): some things are united by species and distinguished by hypostases, [whereas] others are distinguished by species but united by hypostases.29

Finally, Leontius proposed the theory of the interchange of relations, thus writing about the hypostatic and substantial unions and distinctions, which are the reversed counterparts of each other:

It can be discovered that the set of relations of things belonging to different species to things of the same species is interchangeable (ἐπαλλάττουσαν): for in respects in which things of the same species are in common with things of different species, they are distinguished between each other; and in respects in which they are distinguished from things of different species, they are joined to each other. For they are distinguished from each other but joined to things of other species by number, and they are joined to each other but distinguished from things of other species by definition.30

This distinction resulted in three universal pairs of links and distinctions: two relations of the Father to the Word and the Word to the Father, two relations of the Word to the flesh and the flesh to the Word, and two relations of Christ to us and us to Christ. That which connects and distinguishes the relations in the first and third pairs, is opposed to that which connects and distinguishes the relations in the middle pair.31 Leontius again illustrated this concept by the anthropological analogy:

Soul is united to soul by having the same essence, and is distinguished by the difference in hypostasis. This is the first and the final relationship of the pairs. The soul is distinguished from its body by the difference in nature, and is united [to it] by the category of hypostasis, which their mutually coherent life brings into full being. The second or middle relationship preserves this. But man is completely distinguished from his body by itself and his soul by itself as being their totality; because he has the first sort of relationship to his parts, he brings about the second sort of sharing between them.32

John of Damascus not only used the concept of the enhypostaton in his philosophical and Christological treatises, but also followed the analogy of the union of soul and body as a model of two distinct natures actualized in a single human person, and applied the anthropological paradigm to show how the properties of the natures are preserved intact and unaltered in the hypostatic union, be it the union of soul and body in a man, or human and divine natures in Christ, with composite hypostasis in each case securing indivisibility of the union, and immutability of the natural properties. Composite nature, on the contrary, produces a change in the qualities of its constituent components, as is the case with the human body, resulting from the union of four elements. In using the analogy of the soul-body compound, John of Damascus follows the Leontian logic of unions and distinctions:

Thus it is with the hypostasis in the case of the soul and the body, for here one hypostasis is made of both the compound hypostasis of Peter, let us say, or of Paul. This keeps in itself the two perfect natures that of the soul and that of the body and it preserves their difference distinct and their properties unconfused. And in itself it has the characteristic differences of each, those of the soul, which distinguish it from all other souls, and those of the body, which distinguish it from all other bodies. These, however, in no wise separate the soul from the body, but they unite and bind them together, at the same time marking off the one hypostasis composed of them from all other hypostases of the same species. Moreover, once the natures become hypostati-cally united, they remain absolutely indivisible. And this is so because, even though the soul is separated from the body in death, the hypostasis of both remains one and the same. For the constitution in itself of each thing at its beginning of being is a hypostasis. Therefore, the body remains, as does the soul; both always having the one principle of their being and subsistence, even though they are separated <…> And again, it is impossible for things that have once begun to subsist in themselves to have another principle of subsistence, for the hypostasis is subsistence in self.33

Once the hypostasis emerged in the conception and ensoulment in the case of humans,34 or when the hypostasis of the Word assumed human nature as its own in the Incarnation,35 in both cases it remained indissoluble36 and secured the restoration of the union of one’s immortal soul separated from its mortal body in the resurrection. John of Damascus also explains how the two opposing sets of properties coexist in one composite hypostasis of the Son:

…and in our Lord Jesus Christ, the bodily form and visible countenance, and Him being the Son of the Virgin to Him being the Son of God without form, determines not the differences in hypostases, but differences in natures, while separating one hypostasis from those consubstantial to it according to the divinity, that is from the hypostases of the Father and the Holy Spirit, and from hypostases consubstantial to it according to the humanity, that is from the mother and other individual people, for when one composite hypostasis originates from two natures, both, that is to say, natural and hypostatic properties of the divine nature, and of humanity become the constituting properties of the hypostasis. Hence Christ is God and Man, beginningless and having a beginning, one and the same hypostasis, visible and invisible, created and uncreated, limited and boundless, suffering and passionless, the Son of God and the Son of the Virgin, that is, the Son of Man, Motherless from the Father and Fatherless from the Mother, undepictable and in the form of a slave and in the countenance of a man, “fairer than the sons of men” (Ps. 44: 2). All this constitutes and distinguishes the hypostasis of Christ God, and He is named by all [properties] together and by each individual one.37

This treatment of hypostasis with enhypostasized substances, and substance with ensubstantiated hypostases results in a reversed order of relationships at the level of the inner Trinitarian relationships, and the Incarnation: just as hypostases are numerically distinguished in the single substance of the Holy Trinity by their hypostatic properties, substances are numerically distinguished by their substantial properties, preserving their definition of substance in the single hypostasis of Christ after the Incarnation.

All these developments, including the Leontian ontological theology of hypostases with their characteristic properties and enhypostasized substances with their definitions, reversed relationships between unions and distinctions at the hypostatic and substantial levels, were adaped for for the Neo-Chalcedonian Christological doctrine by Maximus the Confessor and were followed by John of Damascus.

John of Damascus has been rightly credited with the reputation of a theologian who was the first to set the apology for icons into a Christological perspective. In his Apologies in defense of icons, John appeals to Christology, and more precisely to the role of Christ's flesh in the Christological union, replying with a typical Neo-Chalcedonian Christological formula to a certain rebuke by someone who stated that the Iconophiles perceived Christ's flesh on the icon as a “garment or a fourth prosopon ” in the manner of Nestorius:

I venerate together with the King and God the purple of [His] body, not as a garment or a fourth person (οὐχ ὡς ἱμάτιον οὐδ’ ὡς τέταρτον πρόσωπον) (God forbid!), but as proclaimed to be and to have become unchangeably equal to God, and the source of anointing. For the nature of the flesh has not become the divinity, but as the Word became flesh immutably, remaining what He was, thus also the flesh became the Word not losing what it was, but rather becoming equal to the Word according to the hypostasis. Therefore I dare to depict the invisible God, not as invisible, but as becoming visible for our sake by participation in flesh and blood.38

A close parallel to the argument of St. John of Damascus in the polemics within the specifically Eastern Syrian context indicates the familiarity of John’s adversary with the Antiochean theological tradition,39 and John’s formulation of the

Christological dimension of the image doctrine vis-à-vis his opponents from the Nestorian and Miaphysite camps in Palestine.

Although it is not yet clear to which extent the theological legacy of John of Damascus was used in Constantinople during the second Iconoclasm,40 concepts used by him such as the uniqueness of Christ as one of the Holy Trinity beyond the species, indissolubility of his hypostasis even when two of its constituent components (body and soul) separated after death until the Resurrection, and appropriation of substantial properties of both natures thus becoming Christ’s own, were used by the Iconophiles of the Second Iconoclasm in formulating several arguments against the Iconoclastic claim that Christ was incirmumscribable. One of the arguments used by both Iconophile champions who left their polemical writings against the Iconoclasts – Patriarch Nicephorus of Constantinople (806–815), and Theodore the Studite (759–826) – employs the “relational” ontology of unions and distinctions of Leontius of Byzantium.

Already Leontius of Byzantium formulated this problem, asking his interlocutor: “When the Logos assumed human nature, did he assume it as seen in the species or as in an individual?”41 One of the Iconoclastic arguments was precisely that Christ assumed only general human nature, without distinguishing features42, which were all that could be depicted on the icon, thus considering the icon of Christ an arbitrary choice of an artist, false from an epistemological viewpoint, and idolatrous from a theological viewpoint.

The symmetrical theological ontology of Leontius entailed a reversed order of relationships: whatever distinguishes hypostases at the level of theologia and human species, unites natures at the level of oikonomia. In the context of the anti-Iconoclastic polemics, this symmetric Christology led to a syllogism: if we confess three hypostases of the Holy Trinity in one substance with its proper definition, and one hypostasis of Christ in two natures, appropriating the “extremes” of both natures including the full sets of substantial properties which become his own, not only can we, but we must confess the opposite substantial properties of his human nature. Thus, the unquestionable Trinitarian formula of the three con-substantial hypostases sharing divine nature with its immaterial, invisible, intangible, incircumscribable, etc. properties, implied a complete set of the opposite human properties, material, visible, tangible, and circumscribable, belonging to one and the same Christ, whose hypostatic properties and therefore the hypostasis, were revealed, named, and venerated on the icon despite the difference in material substance.43 Accordingly, it followed that those who denied the validity of that conclusion, had to inevitably disagree with either of the premises, and therefore side with the heretics of the past – Arians, if they rejected the first premise, or Monophysites if they rejected the second premise. Patriarch Nicepho-rus thus rebukes his Iconoclastic opponents who denied the circumscription of Christ:

As in the economy of the Incarnation, the natures are united in hypostasis, so in the Holy Trinity, the hypostases differ by their personal properties. As in the Holy Trinity, the hypostases are united by the sameness of nature, so in the economy of the Incarnation, natures differ by substantial difference of their properties. Therefore, just as in the Incarnation they [the heretics] do not recognize the distinguishing features of nature, which separate them from beings of a different nature, so in the Holy Trinity they should not at all allow for any distinguishing properties between the hypostases, which set apart the hypostases as considered to be of one and the same substance, from each other. And as they had disagreements about hypostasis then, they also have disagreements about nature now, for they do not see the difference in the distinctive property. What can I say to this? That if, according to their assumption, the flesh should not be circumscribable because of its union with the Word, in the other case [in the Holy Trinity] one has to arrive at similar absurdities, since there one must reason differently than in the case of the Incarnation.44

Theodore the Studite also used the Leontian system of relational oppositions against the accusation of the Iconoclasts that representing Christ on the icon only renders his human aspect and thereby “splits apart” his divinity and humanity in the manner of Nestorius:

For, as in in the Holy Trinity, that which constitutes the properties (τό ἰδιάζον) of the hypostases does not divide the single nature of divinity, but that which shares the commonality by nature is distinguished by hypostasis; in the Incarnation, on the contrary, that which constitutes the properties of nature does not divide the single hypostasis of God the Word, but that which shares the commonality by hypostasis is distinguished by nature. If division were introduced with circumscription which is a property of human nature, accordingly, here too, the Ungeneratedness, the Generat-edness, and the Procession, which are the properties of the three hypostases, would divide the single nature; but, of course, they do not, although they are different from each other. Therefore, here, too, the incircumscribability of the divinity and circumscribability of humanity – although they are different from each other – [do not divide] the hypostasis of Christ.45

However, by applying the Leontian logic of relational unions and distinctions, Theodore the Studite went a step further. He includes the artificial image of Christ into the system of paired relationships at the levels of substance and hypostases, arguing that the sameness of divine substance shared by the Father and the Son, which makes them one God, at the level of theologia , in reversed order of paired relationships at the level of oikonomia entails the sameness of hypostasis for Christ and his image, which makes them one Christ despite the difference in material substrate:46

If, that which distinguishes the Son from the Father – and He is distinguished only by the property of Sonship (τῷ ὑΐκῷ ἰδιώματι), does not harm Him from being of one and the same substance and worship with the Father, that which distinguishes the image from the prototype – and it is distinguished by the definition of substance, does not harm it either from being one and the same likeness and worship with the prototype. As in the former case Christ differs from the Father by hypostasis, in that latter case he differs from his own image by substance.47

Thus, the theological adaptation of the notions of substance and hypostasis from their original Trinitarian to a Christological context by Leontius of Byzantium, involving enhypostasized substance, distinction between the principle of substance and mode of existence, as well as “relational” ontology of unions and distinctions at the levels of substances and hypostases was adopted and reworked by Maximus the Confessor and John of Damascus for articulating the Neo-Chalcedonian position in their Christological polemics. Furthermore, the Icono-philes of the Second Iconoclasm used the relational model of Leontius against the Iconoclastic Christology which claimed that general human nature without distinguishing features was assumed by Christ, leading to his incircumscribability. The use of the Leontian conceptual framework in support of the circumscribabil- ity of Christ, made it possible to postulate not only cirmumscribability and thus the depictability of Christ, but also the unity of his hypostasis and artificial image based on the unquestionable Nicean doctrine of consubstantiality of Persons in the Holy Trinity.

Список литературы The Theological Ontology of Leontius of Byzantium and the Circumscribability Argument in the Iconophile Polemics

  • Abramowski, L. and A. E. Goodman, eds. (1972) A Nestorian Collection of Christological Texts, vol. 2, University of Cambridge Oriental Publications 19, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • von Balthasar H. U. (1988) Kosmische Liturgie. Das Weltbild Maximus' des Bekenners, Einsiedeln, Trier: Johannes-Verlag.
  • Baranov, V. A. (2002) “Theology of Early Iconoclasm as Seen in the Apologies in Defence of Images by St. John of Damascus,” Khristianskij Vostok 4 (10), 23-55.
  • Baranov, V. A. (2020a), “Sources of Fragments by the Iconoclastic Patriarch John Grammaticus (837–843): Leontius of Byzantium,” Schole 14 (1), 278-292.
  • Baranov, V. A. (2020b) “Origenizm Leontiya Vizantijskogo: sostoyanie issledovanij” [Origenism of Leontius of Byzantium: State of research], ESSE: Filosofskie i teologicheskie issledovaniya 5 (1-2) (2020), 188-208.
  • Blowers, P. M. (2016) Maximus the Confessor: Jesus Christ and the Transfiguration of the World, Christian Theology in Context, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Bratu, M. (2003) “Quelques aspects de la doctrine de l'icône de Saint Théodore Stoudite,” Revue des sciences religieuses 77 (3), 323-349.
  • Butler, M. E. (1994) Hypostatic Union and Monotheletism. The Dyothelite Christology of St. Maximus the Confessor, Ph.D. Dissertation, Fordham University.
  • Chase, F. H., Jr., transl. (1958) Saint John of Damascus. Writings, Fathers of the Church Patristic Series 37, Washington, D. C.: The Catholic University of America Press.
  • Choufrine, A. (2003) “The Development of St. Basil’s Idea of Hypostasis,” Studi sull’Oriente Cristiano 7 (2), 7-27.
  • Congourdeau, M.-H. (1989) “L’animation de l’embryon humain chez Maxim le Confesseur,” Nouvelle revue théologique 111, 693-709.
  • Congourdeau, M.-H. (1999) “Sang féminin et génération chez les auteurs byzantins,” in: M. Faure, ed., Le sang au Moyen Âge. Actes de quatrième colloque international de Montpellier Université Paul Valéry, 27–29 novembre 1997, Les cahiers du C.R.I.S.M.A. 4, Montpellier: Association C.R.I.S.I.M.A., Université Paul-Valéry, 19-23.
  • Congourdeau, M.-H. (2007) L’embryon et son âme dans les sources grecques (VIe siècle av. J.-C. - Ve siècle apr. J.-C.), Paris: Association des amis du Centre d’histoire et civilisation de Byzance.
  • Corrigan, K. (2008) “Οὐσία and ὑπόστασις in the Trinitarian Theology of the Cappadocian Fathers: Basil and Gregory of Nyssa,” Zeitschrift für antikes Christentum 12 (1), 114-134.
  • Daley, B. E. (2002) “Nature and ‘Mode of Union’: Late Patristic Models for the Personal Unity of Christ,” in: S. T. Davis, D. Kendall, and G. O’Collins, eds., The Incarnation: An Interdisciplinary Symposium on the Incarnation of the Son of God, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 164-196.
  • Daley, B. E., ed. and transl. (2017) Leontius of Byzantium: Complete Works, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Davydenkov, O. V. (2016) “Termin ‘voipostasnoe’ v khristologicheskikh diskussiyakh pervoi poloviny VI veka” [The term ‘enhypostaton’ in the Christological discussion of the first half of the sixth century], Vestnik RKhGA 17 (3), 11-24.
  • Davydenkov, O. V. (2018) “Ponyatie ‘voipostasnoe’ v difizitskoi khristologii posle Leontiya Vizantiiskogo” [The notion of “enhypostaton” in Dyophisite Christology after Leontius of Byzantium], Khristianskoe chtenie 1, 21-33.
  • Declerck, J., ed. (1982) Maximi Confessoris Quaestiones et dubia, Corpus Christianorum, Series Graeca 10, Turnhout, Leuven: Brepols, University Press.
  • Declerck, J., ed. (1989) Diversorum capitum seu difficultatum solutio, Corpus Christianorum Series Graeca 19, Turnhout, Leuven: Brepols, University Press.
  • Deferrari, R., ed. and transl. (1926) St. Basil. The Letters, Loeb Classical Library, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Dell’Osso, C. (2003) “Still on the Concept of Enhypostaton,” Augustinianum 43 (1), 63-80.
  • Drecoll, V. H. (1996) Die Entwicklung der Trinitätslehre des Basilius von Cäsarea: sein Weg vom Homöusianer zum Neonizäner, Forschungen zur Kirchen- und Dogmengeschichte 66, Göttingen: Vandenhoeck und Ruprecht.
  • Erdin, F. (1939) Das Wort Hypostasis: Seine bedeutungsgeschichtliche Enlwicklung in der allchristlichen Literatur bis zum Abschluss der trinitarischen Auseinandersetzungen, Freiburg im Breisgau.
  • Erismann, C. (2010) “A World of Hypostases: John of Damascus'. Rethinking of Aristotle's Categorical Ontology,” Studia Patristica 50, 251-269.
  • Erismann, C. (2017) “Theodore the Studite and Photius on the Humanity of Christ. A Neglected Byzantine Discussion on Universals in the Time of Iconoclasm,” Dumbarton Oaks Papers 71, 175-192.
  • Erismann, C. (2018) “To Be Circumscribed Belongs to the Essence of Man. Theodore of Stoudios on Individuality, Circumscription and Corporeality,” Jahrbuch der österreichischen Byzantinistik 68, 225-238.
  • Evans, D. B. (1970) Leontius of Byzantium: An Origenist Christology, Dumbarton Oaks Studies 13, Dumbarton Oaks: Dumbarton Oaks, Center for Byzantine Studies, Trustees for Harvard University.
  • Fatouros, G. ed. (1992) Theodori Studitae Epistulae, Corpus Fontium Historiae Byzantinae 31, Berlin, New York: Walter de Gruyter.
  • Featherstone, J. M., ed. (1997) Nicephori Patriarchae Constantinoploitani Refutatio et eversion definitionis synodalis anni 815, Corpus Christianorum. Series Graeca 33, Turnhout, Leuven: Brepols, University Press.
  • Garrigues, J.-M. (1974) “La personne composée du Christ d’après saint Maxime le Confesseur,” Revue thomiste 74, 181-204.
  • Gleede, B. (2012) The Development of the Term Ἐνυπόστατος from Origen to John of Damascus, Supplements to Vigiliae Christianae 113, Leiden, Boston: Brill.
  • Gockel, M. (2000) “A Dubious Christological Formula? Leontius of Byzantium and the Anhypostasis-Enhypostasis Theory,” Journal of Theological Studies 51 (2), 515-532.
  • Grumel, V. (1926) “L'union hypostatique et la comparaison de l'âme et du corps chez Léonce de Byzance et saint Maxime le confesseur,” Échos d'Orient 25 (144), 393- 406.
  • de Halleux, A. (1984) “‘Hypostase’ et ‘personne’ dans la formation du dogme trinitaire (ca. 375-381),” Revue d'histoire ecclésiastique 79, 313-369, 625-670.
  • Hammerstaedt, J. (1994) “Hypostasis,” in: Reallexikon für Antike und Christentum, vol. 16, Stuttgart: A. Hiersemann, 986-1035.
  • Heinzer, F. (1980) Gottes Sohn als Mensch. Die Struktur des Menschseins Christi bei Maximus Confessor, Freiburg.
  • Hovorun, S. (2006) “K istorii termina ἐνυπόστατον ‘voipostasnoe’” [History of the term ἐνυπόστατον, enhypostaton], in: A. R. Fokin, ed., Leontij Vizantiiskij. Sbornik issledovanij [Leontius of Byzantium. Collection of studies], Moscow: Tsentr biblejskopatrologicheskikh issledovanij, Imperium Press, 655-665.
  • Hübner, R. (1972) “Gregor von Nyssa als Verfasser der sog. Ep. 38 des Basilius: Zum unterschiedlichen Verständnis der ousia bei den kappadozischen Brüdern,” in: J. Fontaine and Ch. Kannengiesser, eds., Epektasis: Mélanges à J. Daniélou, Paris: Beauchesne, 463-490.
  • Jones, D. A. (2007) The Soul of the Embryo: An Enquiry into the Status of the Human Embryo in the Christian Tradition, London: Continuum.
  • Khristos, I. (2011) Η έννοια του “ἐνυποστάτου” στον Άγιο Ιωάννη Δαμασκηνό. Thessaloniki.
  • Kotter, B., ed. (1969) Johannes von Damaskos. Institution elementaris. Capita philosophica (Dialectica), Die Schriften des Johannes von Damaskos 1, Patristische Texte und Studien 7, Berlin, New York: Walter De Gruyter.
  • Kotter, B., ed. (1973) Johannes von Damaskos. Expositio fidei. Die Schriften des Johannes von Damaskos 2, Patristische Texte und Studien 12, Berlin, New York: Walter De Gruyter.
  • Kotter, B., ed. (1975) Johannes von Damaskos. Contra imaginum calumniatores orations tres, Die Schriften des Johannes von Damaskos 3. Patristische Texte und Studien 17, Berlin, New York: Walter de Gruyter.
  • Kotter, B., ed. (1981) Johannes von Damaskos. Liber de haeresibus. Opera polemica, Die Schriften des Johannes von Damaskos 4, Patristische Texte und Studien 22, Berlin, New York: Walter De Gruyter.
  • Krausmüller, D. (2011) “Making Sense of the Formula of Chalcedon: the Cappadocians and Aristotle in Leontius of Byzantium’s Contra Nestorianos et Eutychianos,” Vigiliae Christianae 65, 484-513.
  • Krausmüller, D. (2014) “A Chalcedonian Conundrum: The Singularity of the Hypostasis of Christ,” Scrinium 10, 371-391.
  • Krausmüller, D. (2017) “Enhypostaton: Being ‘in Another’ or Being ‘with Another’? How Chalcedonian Theologians of the Sixth Century Defined the Ontological Status of Christ’s Human Nature,” Vigiliae Christianae 71, 433-448.
  • Krausmüller, D. (2018) “On the Relation between the Late Antique and Byzantine Christological Discourses: Observations about Theodore the Stoudite's Third Antirrheticus,” Jahrbuch der österreichischen Byzantinistik 68, 239-250.
  • Krausmüller, D. (2019) “Does the Flesh Possess Hypostatic Idioms, and If So, Why Is It Then Not a Separate Hypostasis? On a Conceptual Problem of Late Patristic Christology,” Scrinium 15, 193-210.
  • Krausmüller, D. (2020) “When Christology Intersects with Embryology: The Viewpoints of Nestorian, Monophysite and Chalcedonian Authors of the Sixth to Tenth Centuries, Byzantinische Zeitschrift 113, 853-878.
  • Krausmüller, D. (2021) “Christ and His Representation, One or Two? The Image Theologies of Theodore of Stoudios, Leo of Chalcedon and Eustratius of Nicaea,” Scrinium 17, 356-371.
  • Lamberz, E., ed. (2016) Concilium Universale Nicaenum Secundum, in Acta Conciliorim Oecumenicorum, series secunda, vol. 3, pt. 3, Berlin, Boston: Walter De Gruyter.
  • Lang, U. M. (1998) “Anhypostatos-Enhypostatos: Church Fathers, Protestant Orthodoxy, and Karl Barth,” Journal of Theological Studies 49, 630–657.
  • Larchet, J.-C. (1996) La divinisation de l'homme selon saint Maxime le Confesseur, Paris: Cerf.
  • Larchet, J.-C. (2018) “Hypostasis, Person and Individual according to St Maximus the Confessor, with reference to the Cappadocians and St. John of Damascus,” in: A. Torrance and S. Paschalidis, eds., Personhood in the Byzantine Christian Tradition, Early, Medieval, and Modern Perspectives, London, New York : Routledge, 47-67.
  • Lebon, J. (1927) “Une ancienne opinion sur la condition du corps du Christ dans la mort,” Revue d’histoire ecclésiastique 23, 5-43, 209-241.
  • Lebourlier, J. (1962-1963) “À propos de l’état du Christ dans la mort,” Revue des sciences philosophiques et théologiques 46, 629-649; 47, 161-180.
  • Lourie, B. (2019) “Theodore the Studite’s Christology against Its Logical Background,” Studia Humana 8 (1), 99-113.
  • Louth, A. (2002) St. John Damascene: Tradition and Originality in Byzantine Theology, Oxford Early Christian Studies, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Louth, A. (2008) “From Doctrine of Christ to Icon of Christ: St. Maximus the Confessor on the Transfiguration of Christ.” in: P. W. Martens, SJ, ed., In the Shadow of the Incarnation: Essays on Jesus Christ in the Early Church in Honor of Brian E. Daley, Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 260-275.
  • Louth, A. (2017) “St. Maximos’ Distinction between λόγος and τρόπος and the Ontology of the Person,” in: S. Mitralexis, G. Steiris, M. Podbielski, and S. Lalla, eds., Maximus the Confessor as a European Philosopher, Veritas 25, Eugene, OR: Cascade Books, 157-165.
  • Madden, N. (1993) “Composite Hypostasis in Maximus Confessor,” Studia Patristica 27, 175-197.
  • Mayhew, R. (2004) The Female in Aristotle’s Biology: Reason or Rationalisation, Chicago, London: University of Chicago Press.
  • Michel, A. (1922) “Hypostase,” in: Dictionnaire de théologie catholique, vol. VII/1, Paris: Letouzey et Ané, 369-437.
  • Otto, S. (1968) Person und Subsistenz. Die philosophische Anthropologie des Leontios von Byzanz; ein Beitrag zur Spätantiken Geistesgeschichte, München: Fink. PG = Migne, J.-P., ed. Patrologiae Cursus Completus. Series Graeca. Venice, 1857-1866.
  • Podbielski, M. (2017) “The Face of the Soul, the Face of God: Maximus the Confessor and πρόσωπον,” in: S. Mitralexis, G. Steiris, M. Podbielski, and S. Lalla, eds., Maximus the Confessor as a European Philosopher, Veritas 25, Eugene, OR: Cascade Books, 193-228.
  • Richard, M. (1945) “L’introduction du mot hypostase dans la théologie de l’Incarnation,” Mélanges de science religieuse 2, 5-32, 243-270.
  • Roosen, B. (2021) “What Theodosius of Gangra Wanted to Know from Maximus the Confessor,” in: B. Demulder and P. Van Deun, eds., Questioning the World. Greek Patristic and Byzantine Question-and-Answer Literature, Lectio. Studies in the Transmission of Texts and Ideas 11, Turnhout: Brepols, 229-267.
  • Rougier, R. (1916-1917) “Le sens des termes οὐσία, ὑπόστασις et πρόσωπον dans les controverses trinitaires post-nicéennes,” Revue d’histoire des religions 73, 48-63; 74, 133-189.
  • von Schönborn, C. (1986) L’icône du Christ: Fondaments théologiques, Paris: Cerf.
  • Shchukin, T. (2016) “Identity in Difference: Substance and Nature in Leontius of Byzantium’s Writings,” Scrinium 12, 308-321.
  • Sherwood, P. (1955) The Earlier Ambigua of Saint Maximus the Confessor and His Refutation of Origenism, Studia Anselmiana 36, Rome: “Orbis Catholicus”/Herder.
  • Solère, J.-L., M.-H. Congourdeau, and L. Brisson, eds. (2008) L’embryon: formation et animation: Antiquité grecque et latine, traditions hébraïque, chrétienne et islamique, Histoire des doctrines de l’Antiquité classique 38, Paris : Vrin.
  • Thunberg, L. (1995) Microcosm and Mediator. The Theological Anthropology of Maximus the Confessor, 2nd ed., Chicago and La Salle, IL: Open Court.
  • Tollefsen, T. T. (2018) St. Theodore the Studite’s Defence of the Icons. Theology and Philosophy in Ninth-Century Byzantium, Oxford Early Christian Studies, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Turcescu, L. (1997) “Prosopon and Hypostasis in Basil of Caesarea’s ‘Against Eunomius’ and the Epistles,” Vigiliae Christianae 51 (4), 374-395.
  • Uthemann, K. H. (1982) “Das anthropologische Modell der hypostatischen Union. Ein Beitrag zu den philosophischen Voraussetzungen und zur innerchalkedonischen Transformation eines Paradigmas,”Kleronomia 14, 214–312.
  • Witt, R. E. (1933) “Hypostasis,” in: H.G. Wood, ed., Amicitiae Corolla: A Volume of Essays Presented to J. R. Harris, London: University of London Press, 319-343.
  • Zachhuber J. (2001) “Basil and the Three-Hypostases Tradition: Reconsidering the Origins of Cappadocian Theology,” Zeitschrift für antikes Christentum 5, 65-85.
  • Zachhuber, J. (2003) “Nochmals: Der 38. Brief des Basilius von Caesarea als Werk des Gregor von Nyssa,” Zeitschrift für antikes Christentum 7 (1), 73-90.
  • Zachhuber, J. (2012) “Individuum und Individualitat in den theologischen Debatten der Spatantike,” in: W.Grab and L. Charbonnier, eds., Individualität. Genese und Konzeption einer Leitkategorie humaner Selbstdeutung, Berlin: Berlin University Press, 13-49.
  • Zachhuber, J. (2014) “Individuality and the Theological Debate about ‘Hypostasis’,” in: A. Torrance and J. Zachhuber, eds., Individuality in Late Antiquity, Farnham: Ashgate, 91-110.
  • Zachhuber, J. (2015) “Christology after Chalcedon and the Transformation of the Philosophical Tradition,” in: M. Knežević, ed., The Ways of Byzantine Philosophy, Alhambra, CA: Sebastian Press, 89-110.
  • Zhyrkova, A. (2009) “Hypostasis – the Principle of Individual Existence in John of Damascus,” Journal of Eastern Christian Studies 61(1-2), 101-130.
  • Zhyrkova, A. (2017a) “Leontius of Byzantium and the Concept of Enhypostaton: A Critical Re-evaluation, Forum Philosophicum 22 (2), 193-218.
  • Zhyrkova, A. (2017b). “John of Damascus’ Philosophy of the Individual and the Theology of Icons,” in: A. Kaldellis and N. Siniossoglou, eds., The Cambridge Intellectual History of Byzantium, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 431-446.
  • Zhyrkova, A. (2019) “The Éminence Grise of Christology: Porphyry’s Logical Teaching as a Cornerstone of Argumentation in Christological Debates of the Fifth and Sixth Centruies,” Journal of Applied Logics – IfCoLog Journal of Logics and their Applications 6(6), 1109-1124.
Еще
Статья научная