Between eternity and divine dualism: Hugh of Saint-Cher’s Opus II, pars I
Автор: Nekhaenko F.
Журнал: Schole. Философское антиковедение и классическая традиция @classics-nsu-schole
Рубрика: Переводы
Статья в выпуске: 1 т.18, 2024 года.
Бесплатный доступ
The paper contains the the first Latin transcription and an English translation of the first part of the second book of Hugh of Saint-Cher's Opus, his commentary on Peter Lombard's Sentences accomplished between 1231 and 1234. The transcription is based on the codex Vat. lat. 1098 collated with five auxiliary manuscripts. In line with William of Auxerre and Alexander of Hales Hugh critically disavows pagan and heretical stances represented by Plato, Aristotle, Epicurus, and Manichean regarding the creation of the world. My foreword sheds light on the philosophical value of presented arguments plus the historical background of the issue and Hugh's relation with contemporary theologians whose ideas Hugh rearranges and modifies in one concise text. I argue that Hugh blends together these four authorities to challenge and reject the concepts of eternity and dualism. The theologian imputes dualism - contrary to the run-of-the-mill attribution of three beginnings - to the Stagyrite while putting the concept of opposite principles from Aristotle referenced before by William in Cathar's mouth. Even Plato and Epicurus become proponents of the heretical repudiation of creation from nothing in favor of divine production from adjacent matter which aligns the Greeks with Cathars' metaphysics. Hugh's Opus, if not original in the modern sense, anticipated a surge of refutations aimed at heretics and “Averroists”. The proposed isomorphism between Aristotle-Heretic and Cathar-Peripatetic partially molded early arguments in the theological Sentences as well as inquisitorial Summa. Whereas the focus on Сathars' dualism diminished when they were brutally wiped off the map, William, Alexander, and Hugh's reasons against the Peripatetic view on eternity continued to draw attention among theologians fighting back “Averroism”.
Hugh of saint-cher, aristotle, eternity, cathars, divine dualism, sentences
Короткий адрес: https://sciup.org/147244488
IDR: 147244488 | DOI: 10.25205/1995-4328-2024-18-1-347-386
Текст научной статьи Between eternity and divine dualism: Hugh of Saint-Cher’s Opus II, pars I
His commentary commonly called Opus or Scriptum deviated from both the conventional literal expositions of the Bible and previous attempts to explicate Peter Lombard's florilegium — 4 books that feature a plethora of authoritative quotes retrieved above all from Augustine, Abelard, and Hugh of Saint-Victor on the Trinity, creation, Christian virtues, church sacraments, and last things — within the genre of glossa or summa. Whereas glossae tied Stephan Langton and Alexander of Hales to Peter's text and limited the scope of their investigation, summae composed by William of Auxerre and Philip the Chancellor drove their authors to problems not always connected with the structure and circuit of Lombard's manual. Hugh of Saint-Cher was the first theologian to graft onto the future scholasticism a commentary in the shape of viable text full of questiones which he diversified with glosses as a part of lectio setting forth the literal meaning of the text2. During such a transitional stage of the Paris educational system prior to mid-century when the Sentences progressively turned into a standard textbook and garnered an official seal of approval, Hugh's glosses were designed to be read in conjunction with Peter Lombard’s original text. As a result, Hugh abbreviated most of the occasional glosses drawn from Peter into brief indications consisting of one-two words “Stich-wortglossen” that a bachelor who studied theology would instantly grasp and fathom in sharp contrast with the explanations in detail required for modern readers. Take as an example the last sentence of the present transcription in the form of Hugh's manuscript and its reconstruction accomplished by me to embrace how it would have been recognized by contemporary theologians:
The manuscript Vat. lat. 1098
Tradens per Moysem et ante tempora significat quomodo enim tempora crearet, si prius non esset exstitisse scilicet deum.
My reconstruction
Horum ergo et similium errorem spiritus sanctus euacuans, ueritatisque disciplinam tradens per Moysem, deum in principio temporum mundum creasse et ante tempora significat, quomodo enim tempora crearet, si prius non esset, eternaliter exstitisse, scilicet deum.
The reconstructed version is twice as long as the concise and pragmatic abbreviation, suggesting that glosses on Peter's text should be grappled together with his own work3, even though I have appended relevant quotes in the footnotes to accompany Hugh's transcription and recuperated them by translation. In any case, his approach inexorably laid the foundation for ensuing commentaries which gradually shifted from expositiones litterales of Lombard's text and focused instead on contemporary debates in the scholastic theology4.
The Path Towards Scholastic Theology
For a long time, theologia had remained a doctrine akin to pagan philosophy that changed only with Abelard: within the 12th-century school advent, the notion was evolving into a dialectical domain of knowledge designed to confront heretics who contradicted the tenets of faith by appealing to the Scripture5. This advent of dialectics gave rise to scholastic theology which stretched a rational examination of theological problems as far as possible at medieval universities where issues concerning the eternity of the world and the number of creators were debated beyond dogmatic perennial refutations which Peter Lombard himself took up: to claim that Moses said in principio creauit answering pagan and heretic's argumentation was no longer sufficient6. Apparently, some scholastic arguments associated with eternity and dualism came from the Patristic philosophy invigorating scholasticism.
The Eastern Church Fathers spilled much ink in developing a body of arguments countering bothersome Aristotle's idea that the world was uncreated. The evolution of hexameronic literature resulted in the assertation proving that the beginning of time exceeds the flow of time itself ἡ τοῦ χρόνου ἀρχὴ οὔπω χρόνος7. In his extant work, John Philoponus onwards went into matter in this assault by displaying that peripatetic time could not predate the creation of the heaven which is measured by a comprehending soul οὐκ ἦν ἄρα χρόνος πρὶν οὐρανὸν ὑποστῆναι, while eternity implies an infinite regress of time moments σημεῖον … ἀδιάστατον καὶ ἀμερὲς8. Latin Fathers expressed more reservation in providing philosophical justification in defiance of eternity9 to such an extent that Ambrosius confined himself to recount Moses' life validating his wisdom and veracity as an author of Genesis, while Bede did not go beyond reiterating Gen. 1:110. Furthermore, the prehistory of scholastic dialectical contribution against the Cathars bears resemblance to the state of polemics over eternity. The issue of dualism existed since the time of Marcion of Sinope and received formidable interest from Augustine among other prominent Fathers whose anti-Manichean corpus was not well-known in the Middle Ages as scholastics engaged in dialectical debates in northern France, particularly Alain of Lille, Alexander Neckam, Évrard of Béthune, William of Auxerre, and
Philip the Chancellor11, had to devise new arguments in the face of the modern heretical polemicists shrouded under the ancient name of Manicheans12. The spin of Church propaganda against the Cathars13 as well as the sole surviving metaphysical tractate composed by a Cathar dated back to the first decades of the 13th century which were coeval with Hugh of Saint-Cher's Opus 14. That being the case, among Paris masters Hugh resided at the genesis of two vital debates that came to fruition with later friars who had to grapple with erroneous views.
Hugh's third talented forbear and chancellor of Notre Dame de Paris Philip poses more difficulties in assessing his impact on Hugh's Scriptum . Unfortunately, we do not dispose of accurate information regarding the date when he finished his Summa de bono . N. Wicki argues that Philip composed it between 1225–1228 before Alexander of Hales' gloss20, although Alexander's editors and some scholars find it challenging to justify these time boundaries decisively21.
Even if we consent that Hugh did read Summa de bono , such a timeline will not betray my insistence that the Dominican friar prone to recur to William and Alexander introduced some novel counterarguments and more to the point a systematic approach to tackling jointly eternity and divine dualism. Given that the
Summa incarnates a project of epistemological inward attack on the dualism assaulted by the former inquisitor active in Southern France22, Philip's critique of the Cathars in the section roughly corresponding to the beginning of Lombard's second book significantly differs from the present transcription flourishing on the ontological arguments. Philip states that 1) two beginnings of evil and good must belong to two different genera which are deemed impossible since genus does not produce beginnings of things; 2) evil cannot be none other than privation of good; 3) the highest evil would be more perfect if it lacked the good that renders the highest evil imperfect; 4) an evil body and a good soul cannot originate from two divinities, particularly in the context of Christ's two natures23. The only similarity I can identify is Anselm's formula of the highest good quo melius excogitari non potest also mentioned by Alexander. Philip pinpoints that the highest good in opposition to the highest evil could be amended by simplicity simplicitatem addita confutat-ing the initial definition of the highest good24 which does not accord with Hugh who expands his grip on the same expression differently. Moreover, Philip and Hugh's positions on Plato and Aristotle sail past each other. In proximity to Alexander, Philip explains away Aristotle's worldview by substituting eternity with the perpetual duration of the created world mundum esse perpetuum et non eternum 25. The Paris Chancellor endorses the argument that in a perpetual world a beginning is still necessary because perpetuity does not preclude the existence of the begin-ning26. Both Plato and Aristotle are understood to assert the eternity of the world merely in the divine mind which aims to create it eternally27. The final proof deus ab eterno uoluit et potuit, et sciuit facere resonates for the second time with the proposition in Hugh's transcription, though the Dominican perhaps rejects and redefines Chancellor's assumption in turn. I dare to argue two versions of events could have taken hold: 1) if Philip wrote Summa before Hugh, then the Dominican theologian would correct the Chancellor and denounce Aristotle's amalgamation within Christian creationism; 2) alternatively, Hugh's hostility toward new translations would imbue Philip to think out how to reconcile the Stagyrite with Moses, had Philip finished his opus after Hugh. Be that as it may, we should dive into the genealogy, structure, and philosophical content of Hugh's approach.
Aristotle-Heretic
Hugh of Saint-Cher's distinction summons four authorities to refute: Plato, Aristotle, Epicurus, and Manichean who all commit an error related to the beginning of the world principium [2]. By thoroughly envisaging the arguments advanced by Hugh's adversaries, I will cast light on the elements that form a cohesive conjunction of all auctoritates into one isomorphism erected on the ground of dualism and eternity. It is not fortuitous that even at the beginning of Hugh's distinction the deliberate arrangement of four foes in the consecutive order serves to eloquently underscore the kinship of those under delusion eliminated by Moses.
Hugh dogmatically disavows the conception allegedly held by Plato and Epicurus that God creates acting on the eternal matter with an old argument according to which creating in a proper sense creare signifies making from nothing de nichilo aliquid facere [11]. Philosophers assume God to be a human-like agent that would make his absolute power conditioned omnipotens non esset. Hugh specifies that platonic God resembles a human or angelic producer factor who works upon adjacent matter ex preiacenti materia [29], once again a distinctive feature of Thierry of Chartres' approach to the platonized creation from matter waiting to be put into use31. In Abelardian theology, the terms “create” creare and “make” facere entail the same meaning but have different connotations when applied to the divine essence and accidental creatures. In God, to create denotes the necessary will from which the temporal effect proceeds uoluntatem eius necessario sequitur effectus [30]. Thus, reducing divine power to the status of a demiurge would add an accidental property that ties God with creatures and destroys the difference between voluntary creation and production which renders the creature's relation to God in time. Augustine summoned against the Greeks claims that God cannot become a cause of human degradation without a corresponding human decline whence Hugh distinguishes two meanings. Ad litteram reading approves that eternal volition presumes an upright action and outcome. God could want eternally and bring about the world at a particular moment of time. The figurative sense concerns exclusively human discourse wherein only the human relation habitudo undergoes a change, while divine unity remains unaltered. God appertains to different things in the same manner but creatures are prone to modify their attitude. In a nutshell, what God creates eternally and voluntarily without movement or change reflects a temporal and accidental production from the creatures' perspective.
Likewise, Epicurus' account of infinite beginnings and eternal matter is refuted together with Plato's proclaimed edifice and at first glance poses no difficulty. Pierre le Mangeur's implantation of Epicurus in Genesis might elucidate why Hugh familiar with Comestor decides to call on Epicurus32, though it fails to unravel why Epicurus insists on the divine creation from matter in place of atoms and void, as acknowledged by both Comestor and William of Auxerre later33. An alternative explanation for the role Plato and Epicurus play would make more sense: the Cathars mounted a defense of the proclaimed Plato-Epicurus' position by making use of similar expressions creare sicut facere , factor , and ex preiacenti materia when referring to God [29]34. The learned Cathars presumably voiced these ideas in the Liber de duobus principiis composed by a disciple of Jean de Lugio, that is a “full-blooded” heretical intellectual, in the 1230-s. I cannot eliminate the possibility that Jean's teaching reached Paris before his lectures were compiled into the text we know nowadays as we have some evidence from the scholars acknowledging Cathar's “artistic” appeal to dialectics and philosophy35. However the testimonies of actual Catharic learning are to be explained, addressing the roots of the heretical position found in the Antiquity would outbalance dealing with contemporary heretics, even if they de facto knew Aristotle beyond Liber de causis . This treatment of authorities also lights up the integration of Aristotle into Cathars' discourse.
The exposition of Aristotle's vindication of eternity is not devoid of inherent ambiguity [3]. Aside from relying on William and Alexander's words, Hugh could have direct access to Aristotle's perspective on eternity via translations of “Physics”
and Averroes' “Long Commentary on the Metaphysics” where a clear original expression that denotes infinite time ἄπειρον χρόνον was substituted by infatigabile in Aristotle36 and non accidit ei fatigacio in Averroes37. Meanwhile, a coincident suspicion of Aristotle's innocent creationism, albeit in passing, betrays a hint of caution in Hugh's commentary on Petrus Comestor’s Historia scholastica (1230–1235): here the Parisian master (taking a retreat and surrendering himself to Alexander-Philip's camp?) explicitly resists the line of interpretation according to which Aristotle corroborates the eternal existence of the world operatur sine fine contrary to what Comestor suggests that begs the question38. In that space of time, Hugh might have changed his opinion upside-down or underlined an equivocal distinction between Arabic influence and innocuous Aristotle that seems quite unlikely. Otherwise, I cannot rule out that someone within Hugh’s team at St. Jacques immersed in preparing the commentary pushed forward such an exoneration of Aristotle.
Anyway, I point your attention to the fact that in the Opus Hugh articulately ventures an objection to Aristotle accompanied by anonymous followers qui, cum eo ponunt [3], if he does not resort to a mere rhetorical device, that might cover a vestige of Philip the Chancellor, Alexander of Hales, and unknown members of the faculty of arts39 who could have embarked on redeeming Aristotle before Hugh and fueled the theological reaction. Both Hugh's contemporaries and his personal acquaintance with Aristotle's books fostered discussions and the initial dialectical rebuttal of eternity in the Sentences defended in 1231 precisely when Gregory IX lifted the ban over reading Aristotle's Libri naturales at the faculty of arts to turn away theologians from peripatetic philosophy40.
At first, a reader might assume that Hugh's opposition to Aristotle revolves around the problem of three peripatetic beginnings41, namely matter, form, and operator materia, forma et operatorium dictum [29] which again represents the Chartres' doctrine Peter Lombard aims to attack42. Hugh then pushes forward that these principles can be reduced to two causes of the creation: one passive and the other active. Neither Peter Lombard nor Stephen Langton and Alexander of Hales suggest such a reduction to two beginnings that brings concord between Aristotle and Manichean's outlooks. It deserves highlighting that for the Cathars God along with matter and form preceded the world in eternity43 that corresponds to reinterpreted Aristotle who invokes two beginnings instead of three. Only the fact that the Cathars accept three consecutive creations which Hugh totally elides would discern them from Aristotle's conception of the eternal uncreated world.
Onwards, I suppose that Hugh continues to discredit Aristotle by inchoately speculating on the ambivalence of the notion dictum in relation to operatorium [31]. When induced by Lombard, Latin dictum can be interpreted as either an adjective or a noun. On the one hand, taken as an adjective describing operatorium , it contradicts the catholic faith since God finds himself called operator who acts on existing matter. On the other hand, assumed to be a noun, dictione operatorium embodies the Christian conception of divine creation through saying and creating simultaneously, as exemplified by the famous repetition of dixit in Genesis, although the second beginning remains coeternal with operator still not equal to Christian God.
These passages bear a resemblance to literal glossae on Peter's text providing the reader with an easily accessible clarification of the text Hugh refills with new questions which expand beyond Lombard's scope44. The nexus of the polemics over Aristotle comprises four arguments and three suitable counterarguments. In lieu of glosses, Hugh of Saint-Cher's Opus II.1 furnishes a sample of early university dialectics embodied by William and Alexander when one adduces several reasons to be demolished in light of the author's position. Aristotle's philosophy sparks the first series of arguments and counterarguments. [3] Having cited the second book of “On the Generation and Corruption” where Aristotle claims that “everything which has a likeness to itself is inborn to produce everything similar”, theologians conclude that the beginning of the world as the first cause prima causa must exist from eternity (ab eterno fuit principium mundi). If God is eternal, then everything he creates should possess identical qualities. The second argument [4] echoes William of Auxerre, Alexander of Hales, and Philip the Chancellor's claims according to which potency, knowledge, and will required to create something were in God in eternity, therefore, he could create and in fact he created eternally. The argument transitions from potency which is not temporal since time has not yet come into existence to the actual state of the coeternal world. Next proposition [5] draws upon the authority of Augustine whose quote “we exist because God is good” the masters leverage to the temporal modality: God is eternally good and, consequently, we retain the same eternal predicate. [6] By equating God with the neoplatonic highest good which outflows down to the level of corporal creatures, op-ponens infers that eternal emanation results in the world itself, hence the world must exist forever (ab eterno fluxit, sed eius effluxio nichil aliud est quam mundi).
The inclusion of the term effluxio in the final argument indebted to pseudo-Di-onysius' De divinis nominibus resonates with the first argument where they appeal to prima causa . Both notions stem from the Arabic assimilation of Aristotle and not from Augustine's terminology, as William suggests45. In all likelihood, these Latin notions representing Arabic fayḍ and al-'illa al-ūlā made their debut in the translation carried out by Gerard of Cremona of the Liber de causis , a pseudo-Aris-totle's paraphrase extracted from Proclus46. I presume William and afterwards Alexander with Hugh avouch to unspecified fontes , as at least Avicebron and Avicenna in conjunction with their Spanish translator Dominicus Gundissalinus harmonized Aristotle's teaching with neoplatonic principles of the first cause and the emanation of the good fluxing onto intelligences, thereby creating the world in virtue of their mediation47. Furthermore, in 1982 R.A. Gauthier revealed that Hugh could have cited Averroes' metaphysical commentary to draw a boundary between the motion of physical bodies and the metaphysical movement of angels, ipso facto encapsulating the nascent theological tenets of Averroes' authority which had plagued Paris from 122548. Nonetheless, distinctions II.1–2 reckon an opposite trend. In the second distinction, the Dominican discards Aristotle's conception of eternity within his explication of time as a succession of moments. No time flow would take place for no action and no movement could transpire in eternity being the state of unchanging things status permanens in eodem esse 49. In the present distinction, responsio and three counterarguments bring to ruin the neoplatonized vindication of eternity which lured both Alexander and Philip.
The friar wards off [7] that the world made from necessity must have a beginning in time. [8] The principle of production of the same by the same functions exclusively in the natural order (tenet in naturalis) and does not amount to voluntary agents who operate beyond the constraints of physics. In Hugh's view, metaphysical agents acting with free will like separated souls, angels, and God are not bound by the necessity that Aristotle's reasoning requires. [9] On the footing of the Summa aurea, Hugh contends that God as the voluntary cause with a delayed effect dilatoria chooses prelegit the moment when the world will have been created, unlike creatures who desire and make immediately. To enhance the point, the Dominican goes on claim that the proposition “God desired to make the world from eternity, thus he made it thereby” has different meanings being composed and divided, a celebrated fallacy classified by Aristotle in the De Sophisticis Elenchis. Hugh implies the following self-contradiction: his opponents fall short to logically justify a transition from the eternal will to the act of creation itself, hence the will signifies a potency that does not necessarily correspond to action in quality and time. Divided, the temporality of the will would differ from the act of creation, while composed, it would sound that both proceed from eternity. To back up the orthodoxy, the Dominican efficiently combines authority of his predecessors and logic circumventing a proposition reminiscent of Philip through Aristotle50. Passing by the third reason Hugh abruptly shifts an inconclusive discussion to investigate tout à coup the issue of emanation. If I were a theologian addressing Augustine's quote, I would suggest that divine goodness and our goodness are said equivocally because divine goodness, being the cause of our existence, cannot mirror creatures who would then become semi-gods which goes against divine omnipotence and unicity. Moreover, Augustine emphasizes that these two bonitates are not the same: we aspire to his goodness and God uses us usum nostrum refert for his own goodness which is supreme transcending our existence51. [10] The last counterargument revises emanation through the lens of the three actions apt to the Trinity summe bonitatis triplex est effluxio, namely Son's generation, Spirit's spiration, and Father's creation. The highest perfection always participates in the generation and spiration, though the creation occurs in time as we have already seen that God desires to create eternally by choosing one germane moment. Thereby, our world is a small drop of divine goodness parua stilla bonitatis dei not venting the totality of the divine perfection embodied in the Trinity. Generally, creation can only be accidentally attributed to creatures because it contravenes divine eternity and the highest goodness.
Amid the three ancient sages discussed, though Hugh connects Plato and Epicurus with issues concerning eternal matter and divine predication which touch the friar in relation to Cathars' metaphysics, like a cornerstone Aristotle captures all the vigor and attention paid to gainsay his arguments presented by his progenitors. It is Aristotle alongside the flood of his Arabic and scholastic proponents (their precise list remains illegible) who occupies the place of the villain in this Paris narrative. After all, the Dominican succeeds in what Aristotle resembles Cathars' eternal dualism. Hugh's contribution extends beyond Aristotle-Heretic since our theologian takes into consideration Manichean-Peripatetic from a philosophical point of view encompassing a more comprehensive exploration of the issues at hand.
Manichean-Peripatetic
Stricto sensu heresy (αἵρεσις) denotes a choice regarding Christian dogmas and Scripture reading condemned by councils. So, to demonstrate the disparity between the Bible and its heretical interpretation would be a straightforward means to assail the heretic's stronghold. Nevertheless, in this distinction, Hugh's generation opts for a strategy I have called afore scholastic theology wherein he systematically and rationally proves that Manichean's arguments for two beginnings, namely good and evil gods, lack philosophical foundation [2, 12] as if Manichean were Aristotle. Playing the devil's advocate, Hugh starts by delivering three already designed arguments that Manichean might propose to secure his position. In the Quoniam homines and De fide catholica , Alain of Lille had come up with the reasons [13] and [14] which then adjusted William of Auxerre, while the [15] Aristotelian idea invoked for the first time by John Blund appeared in connection with heretics only in the Summa aurea antedating Hugh52. Foremost [13], invariable causes result in immutable effects. Analogically, the invariable good could not create a variable or visible. Goodness must remain good within itself since a change of any ilk would imply that it does not have a good inside and seeks something external. [14] Nothing could pretend to be the cause of the creation and destruction of the same. If God created evil people, he would not be able to eradicate them. This limping proposition [14] raises a variety of issues overly easy to dismiss. It imposes stark limitations on the divine omnipotence and makes God the cause of evil beings which clashes with the initial Manichean's premise that all evil originates from malevolent God. Ultimately [15], opposite things give rise to mutual oppositions, then a good God can only create good things and something else is required to account for the existence of evil entities. Again, this reasoning in line with the broader Cathartic logic diminishes the divine power to create.
When I finished the transcription, what William and Hugh's Manichean had referenced Aristotle went unnoticed. In the first instance, the citation has been identified in the Summa aurea by P. Biller who held forth that the Cathars themselves might have alluded to the De generatione et corruptione without any robust testimony on the side of their discourse53. Albeit the general correctness of the reference and the fact that Hugh quotes this work, the proposition сontrariorum con-traria sunt principia [15] reiterates a celebrated idea as well found in the “Meta-physics”54 that being and substance entia et substancia, one and many unum et multa, heat and cold calidum et frigidum like all beginnings are opposite principles principia sunt contraria rendering without significant alteration original τὰς ἀρχὰς ἐναντίας. Moreover, being, a fundamental object of the metaphysical inquiry unius scientia, manifests itself as either opposites or things that arise from opposites aut sunt contraria, aut ex contrariis55. Save that William of Auxerre might have been a pioneering theologian in citing Aristotle-Averroes' “Metaphysics”56, William utilized the same as in Aristotle's tractate example of heat and cold omitted by Hugh57. The reception of the first philosophy not only attests to the position as regards the early influence noted by Gauthier but also sustains my approach to the merger of Aristotle and Manichean: Aristotelianism speaks for Catharism prior to being dismissed by the theologians. By associating contemporary heretics with Greek philosophers, it becomes easier to discredit their beliefs. The Dominican, much like scholastic theologians of his time, implements a common strategy of constructing a figurative representation by borrowing elements from different standpoints which he then accommodates to effectively dismantle and refute all of them.
In response, Hugh takes off the kid gloves to furnish his counterarguments. [16] is valid exclusively in causes connected with their effects in causis coniunctis suis effectibus. This does not serve universally so far as a cause does not necessarily coincide with its effect: for instance, a living being can create a house deprived of what we commonly expect from animated creatures. God as well does not produce creatures who would correspond to his attributes including immutability. Furthermore, motion and mutation are caused by the motionless and immutable divine substance. To initiate a motion a certain element in the chain of moving things should remain at rest; otherwise, a Cathar would find himself trapped in an infinite regress. Hugh's ensuing reason [17] does not prove true for voluntary agents as in the case of an artisan who has the ability to destroy the same thing he made before. Therefore, it falls within God's dominion to willingly create someone who is not equal to his majesty and whom he is in power to thwart. [18] Holding the trump card Hugh incorporates Aristotle against Aristotle in contrast with William who starts with the tantamount primis contrariis and then proceeds that bad cannot secure a positive attribute other than nothing and privation of good: according to Hugh, first opposite things should have a common origin to avoid an infinite regress processus esset infinitum, a celebrated Aristotelian argument originally employed against Zeno's actual infinity58. If on every succeeding level two opposite things stem from opposites without a principle they share, there would be no end in the circuit of causes that contradicts even heretical binarism of beginnings. Alternatively, if each multiplied opposition were to account for an independent beginning, the number of principles would equal the number of opposites tot essent principia, quot sunt contraria which goes against Manichean's dualism as well.
The obtrusive and abrupt intermezzo of glosses [19] precedes Hugh's counterresponse and arguments which carry on a new spin of the discussion [20]. That said, the Dominican friar is committed to acknowledging [21] that the uniqueness of God's essence leaves no room for another equal principle to coexist. The superabundance of God's nature estranges any possibility of something similar existing side by side with him. In his pursuit of truth, a genuine theologian should exhaust all the possibilities to obtain the truth, so Hugh advises to [22] imagine the multiplicity of the highest goods as a logical counterpart of the Cathar's dualism. For Hugh, these highest goods must stay different; otherwise, they would fall into one and the same highest good and lose their identity. Each highest good should differ from another in possessing a particular quality that another highest good would not possess. However, this quality could not be anything else than good itself since any highest good contains only things that are good. Consequently, if one highest good were to obtain a particular good that another highest good did not have alio bono careret , the second beginning would not meet the criterion for the highest good. There is no reason for supposing manifold good beginnings.
Beyond that, maneuvering forward in the stream of discussion, the heretics ex-egetically excogitate [23] that an evil God created the heavens and all visible things enlisted by Moses in the book of Genesis. Hugh fends off [24] that by their definition God is one better than which could not be thought. To what his visionary adversary [25] raises an objection according to which two beginnings exist since two oppositions cannot share the same root turning us back to the third argument proposed by a far-fetched rival [15].
As we move into, Hugh continues this mental ping pong to secure a victory in this dispute akin to a Russian doll by the level of complexity that would try the reader's patience. The fact that Hugh's dualistic opponens has survived up to the fourth circle of the iteration bears witness to an unpreceded involution compared to his less intricate distinctions. Back to the disputation, jumping from a springboard erected on William and Alexander's considerations that an ability to resist bad is good itself59 Hugh brings up the following [27]: if the good God were unable to overcome evil with good, he would be deprived of this goodness and would no longer maintain his status as the highest good. Up to this moment, the master has clung for the second time to Boethius-Anselm's enunciation “better than which nothing greater can be conceived” put to use in the same context by Alexander of Hales and Philip the Chancellor as a definition Manichean adapts to the good God60. Notably, I cannot detect a resembling formula in the existing Cathar's corpus. I expect that our theologians might have thought out this embellished straw man based on the notion of the highest good which cannot exist without being greater than conceivable goodness. Hugh also leaves open another possibility from [27] to excoriate that God could restrain evil since it would strip the evil God of his sovereignty. The second ramification [28] provides an advanced retaliation when Hugh ascertains that the capacity to tackle evil is the power of good itself. Ergo, one of the gods does not bear anymore the status of the highest and Manichean in a monotheistic pitfall has to approve either the good or the bad God.
Historically, the Manichean position may sound more appealing and straightforward to comprehend than the divine creation and ensuing fall of evil angels which enkindled numerous scholastic strifes61. Notwithstanding, William, Alexander, and Hugh have efficiently displayed that God a priori should be unique and single. Even if God were the highest evil, he would still remain the only highest evil.
The Afterlife of Isomorphism
In the title, the word “between” marks the mutual chiasm of eternity and dualism. Hugh introduces significant amendments to both the genre of the Sentences and the questions over which a theologian should enter into consideration. Whatever historical impeachment was issued against Hugh before, armed with Alexander and William's insights the friar has turned what was previously restricted to a gulf between wrongheaded and Moses into a new plane of abstract and sophisticated uprooting of two interlocking problems: eternity and divine dualism. Founded on the divine voluntary essence distinct from natural agents and the world itself, the first set of seven proofs and counterarguments challenges the conception of the eternal world held by Aristotle, Arabs, and Peripatetics. The second impressive list of thirteen reasons suffices to aplenty bring an end to Manichean's stonewalling against which Hugh calls on a variety of arguments centered on the ontological incongruity between divine omnipotence and heretical binarism. I presume the friar entwines a convoluted array of anti-Christian foes into a cohesive isomorphism wherein Plato with Epicurus answer for the Cathar's reduction of creare to facere ex materia, Aristotle endorses dualism, and Manichean maintains the “metaphysics” of opposites. In the aftermath, his toil has withstood the test of time: forty copies of the Opus have come down to us outnumbering even Alexander of Hales' Sentences62, whilst Hugh's œuvre served as the grist to the mill for an educational manual “On the Ground” Filia Magistri63 not to mention several anonymous writ-ings64, mendicant preaching65, and alleged John of la Rochlle's Sentences where the repetition of Hugh de verbo follows an advanced elaboration on the different approaches to eternity introduced through Plato, Aristotle, Boethius, Avicenna, and Averroes. A precise reprint in the case of the Manicheans prepares a covered attack on Hugh's critique of Aristotle. On the surface, John of la Rochelle reiterates four of Hugh's arguments. Notwithstanding, the Franciscan turns around these tenets contrary to anonymous eternity proponents and not against innocent Aristotle who is acknowledged to believe the world to be everlasting sempiternus or perpetuus. Not to mention that John equates Aristotle-Hugh's operatorium with deum, he also completes the counterargument grounded on Augustine [5] with the causality of goodness and furnishes two additional reasons about coeternity and eternal matter. I cannot avoid mentioning that, while sabotaging the anti-Aristotelian camp, John also takes pains to accomplish an impressive synthesis of authorities to decipher Gen. 1:1 with the help of philosophical tools66.
I have discovered that problems illuminated in the present distinction set up a precedent and without sinking into oblivion continued to attract the attention of masters thereafter Hugh had departed from the university. As scholastics did not favor citing their myriad contemporaries by name, approaching later authors I search for similar anonymous questions, arguments, and chiasm structuring anti-Catharic literature as well as later Sentences manuscripts of Odo Rigaud and Peter Aureol which await to be edited. Hugh's fruitful reasoning reverberated to some extent in the aforementioned theologians who propagated multifarious strategies to discuss not only Manichean but also Aristotle and his proponents. Besides, what three foreground representatives of “la nouvelle théologie” Albert the Great, Bonaventure, and Thomas Aquinas67 in their Sentences (approx. 1245–1257) were affected by threads of the chiasm splicing Aristotle and Manichean goes without say-ing68 but more consideration should be devoted to figures who were overshadowed by successors, less studied by scholars, and yet magnifying our ignorance paved the way for a body of thought labeled as scholastic “vanguard”69 who even took the genre quintessence of their divisio textus which consists of several questions and at the end exposition of Peter Lombard's phrasing exemplified by early scholastics Richard Rufus and Odo Rigaud70. My modest contribution supplements an established by L. Bianchi and R. Dales overview of the debates over eternity. However, their splendid and distinguished survey did not include the texts I display here nor did it cover the associated issue of dualism71. Inside the Sentences composed environ 1245, in conformity with Alexander and Hugh Odo Rigaud rehearses three divine eternal predicates and Augustine's argument about divine goodness in correlation with our existence72. Concerning Manichean, he says that opposite beginnings produce contrary phenomena such as preservation and destruction and that good is a power to restrain evil (potestas cohibendi mala)73. Presented ideas, indeed, reached the shore of England when Richard Rufus in the Oxfordian Lectura iterated that like begets like and the world was eternally creatable creabilis and knowable subiectus sciendi before being temporally created. Despite this, the Franciscan friar vanished off the Cathars from the distinction and delivered a totally different speculation about eternity through primum nunc later condemned at Paris74. Both aforementioned Sentences from time to time march in lockstep with Hugh and his masters' isomorphism better exemplified in anti-heretical tractates.
Dominican Moneta of Cremona integrated Aristotle's eternity into Cathar's intellectual agenda75. He played a prominent role as William and potentially Hugh's successor on several occasions. Nevertheless, I cast doubt on P. Biller's suggestion that Roland of Cremona functioned as a mediator between Parisian theology and Italian inquisition76. Such a theory is disrupted due to factual incongruities regarding Roland (the date and place of the composition of his Summa are definitely after 1228 and outside of Paris) that the scholar commits. Given that Roland does concede to arguments similar to William and Hugh, his formulas for immutability, contraries, and divine will to make the world differ from those employed by Paris master and Moneta77. What is more, Roland's Summa is inimitably exceptional for idiosyncratic arguments derived from natural philosophy and imagination. Roland invents unique and exceptional arguments while mocking that Aristotle took a vulnerable view regarding eternity just to insult Plato78. For instance, if the world were to be eternal, there would be an infinite human population without a limit, so that God would cease to endow bodies with rational souls whose number is finite. Take another example, Noah's flood, which took place 10000 years ago according to Roland's calculations, affected terrestrial fertility and transformed human eating habits but it was the one-of-a-kind event determined by celestial constellation. Nonetheless, be the world perpetual, all motions and phenomena must be repeated unceasingly79. Thus, the question of the direct source of Moneta's inspiration retains its relevance80. Specifically, in agreement with William and Hugh, Moneta recaps ad litteram Aristotle's argument about opposite beginnings contrar- iorum contraria sunt principia and peripatetic duality, i.e. operator acting on existing matter81. Hereafter, he follows their heels by rehearsing an opposition of the evil and good God, quia Deus bonus est attributed to unknown philosophers, divine eternal outflow ab aeterno influit, and three eternal instances in God potentia, sa-pientia, voluntas required for the Artisan Artifex to turn into action82. The Italian inquisitor struggles to copy interwoven handling of Aristotle and Manichean deprecating those who strive to redeem the philosopher quidam nitantur Aristotelem excusare and assume the perpetuity of the world mundus totalis perpetuus, a clearcut feature of Alexander of Hales and Philip the Chancellor83. Fortified by the Christian dogma, Hugh's isomorphism confronts such views merging Cathar's theology and Aristotle's metaphysics, though to my surprise the present investigation corroborates J.-P. Torrell's discovery that reasons borrowed by Hugh from mature masters had a way more effect than his original contribution84.
Shifting the timeline, I will present Peter Aureol's testimony extracted from the long Sentences commentary (ca. 1320), a paragon of scholastic intellection, in order to better apprehend the topos of issues elucidated by Hugh. While the axis of dualistic heresy completely disappears from the first distinction, Doctor Facundus still reserves the prologue and first question for the discussion of Aristotle, Averroes, and eternity. Notwithstanding, he demonstrates through cutting the Gordian knot that all a priori arguments including divine freedom of choice promoted by Duns Scotus, the succession of present moments, and the difference between God and the world do not contradict non repugnat eternity85. Conversely, he proposes that if one took into account the possibility of eternity, it would require grappling with a posteriori paradoxes like the inextinguishable nascence of human beings, endless actual division, the unending duration of creatures, and the absence of measure86. Peter Aureol's analysis yields valuable insight into the evolution of scholastic thought enshrining certain of William, Alexander, and Hugh's ideas even in the form of rejected anonymous a priori arguments at the same part of the Sentences. Onwards, medieval history might puzzle out why Hugh of Saint-Cher's chiasm did not endure in the long run, as became apparent in Thomas' Sentences. By the beginning of the 14th century, the Cathars had been razed to the ground, leaving no one to stand up for them in the throes of theological debates. Though, in a larger sense the vogue for lingering issues that surround eternity and the double truth doctrine87 continued to blossom and proliferate with novel university generations throughout the Late Middle Ages.
Editio Hugonis
The second book of Hugh of Saint-Cher's Sentences has received undeservedly the least attention among the four books. Hugh's distinction II.1 has been known exclusively through its incipit prepared by M. Bieniak88. The present edition based on the collation of six manuscripts, all available to me, contains the first part of the second book, whereas the distinction goes on. However, I have decided not to include the rest since there Hugh above all focuses on illuminating Peter Lombard's text in the form of traditional literal exposition rather than amplifying independent issues. The part I have included provides a coherent and insightful elaboration without extensive hermeneutics.
I avail the following sigla to designate the manuscripts: Vat. lat. 1098 = V , BNF lat. 3073 = P 1 , Brugge 178 = B , Assisi 130 = A 1 , Assisi 131 = A 2 , BNF lat. 10728 = P 2 . VP 1 A 1 A 2 account for a family of peciae (a number of authorized copies replicate one codex for future partial borrowing by students) sharing a common exemplar from the Universitätsbibliothek Leipzig (MS 573) and bearing tenets of students' loan. This includes notae and auctoritates written in the margins not to mention opinions of other masters, in particular Guerric of Saint-Quentin. A2 was widely accommodated by the Franciscans and Federico Visconti. B is also a pecia assumedly deriving from another exemplar which enfolds different readings and a complete version of the Quaestio de dotibus resurgentium abridged in VP 1 A 1 A 2 . P 2 stands out as a separate textual tradition since it comprises exclusively the second books preceded by tractates on moral theology89. Manuscript V has been chosen as the basic codex for its readability and clarity. All reading variants are given in the apparatus criticus accompanied by the apparatus fontium where I have put references to the
Latin sources. In the translation, I have checked out existing English versions of Hugh of Saint-Cher's references; I have also attempted to use the closest English terms possible to render Latin theological and philosophical notions without altering the technical and formal style of the scholastic distinction.
I have synchronized the grammar, punctuation, and paragraph division of the transcription with modern standards. The medieval spelling has been preserved, all quotations and references are italicized. To make the text more accessible, I have split up the polemics against Aristotle and Manichean into small paragraphs90 where Roman numerals signify Hugh's arguments. Proper names begin with capital letters except for nomina sacra . ( ) denotes editorial notes, | | stays for the start of a new column, < > indicates editor's supplements to the Latin text. Now, I hope you will allow Hugh of Saint-Cher to speak for himself and claim your interest.
HUGO DE SANCTO CARO
OPUS. LIBER II. DISTINCTIO I. PARS PRIMA91
Incipit secundus liber.
-
1. Creationem rerum etc. Postquam magister egit de creatore, agit de creaturis hoc ordine. Primo auctoritate scripture probat unum esse principium omnium contra quosdam pholosophos, qui ponunt plura principia rerum. Secundo ostendit causam creatoris rerum, ubi dicit92 et quia non ualet 93 et cetera | 45vb |. Tercio quod rerum quedam est spiritualis, ut angelus, quedam corporalis, ut elementa et similia, quorumdam partim spiritualis, partim corporalis, ut homo. Primo inter hec agit de spirituali, id est de angelis. Quarto expedit se de creatione rerum corporalium94. Quinto et ultimo de homine plura dicturus diffusius exequitur95.
-
2. Probans ergo unum auctoritate scripture,96 ait unum esse omne principium, per quod multorum elidit errores. Aristoteles dixit97 mundum esse eternum, cuius error eliditur, ubi dicitur in principio 98. Plato dixit tria esse principia, scilicet deum, ydeas et puram materiam, scilicet ylem99, cuius error eliditur, ubi dicit creauit . Creare enim est de nichilo aliquid facere et ita non de materia100. Epicurus101 ponit102 infinita esse principia, cuius error similiter eliditur, cum dicit creauit103 . Manicheus104 dixit duo esse principia: unum bonorum, quod uocauit105 bonum deum siue deum lucis, siue deum Noui Testamenti106, et hunc dicebat107 tantum esse108 principium spiritualium rerum; alterum malorum, quem uocauit deum
-
3. Aristoteles111 et qui, cum eo ponunt mundum eternum, decepti fuerunt, quia rationes naturales adoptabant deo, sicut patet in secundo De Generatione et Corruptione, ubi supponitur112 hec propositio tanquam per se nota: Idem 113 similiter omnino se habens, natum114 est omnino idem facere 115. Sed prima causa omnino similiter semper se116 habet, immutabilis enim est117. Ergo si aliquando fuit principium mundi et semper fuit principium mundi118, ergo ab eterno fuit principium mundi119.
-
4. Item ad hoc, ut artifex exeat in actum, susficiunt tria120, scilicet potencia, sciencia, uoluntas. Sed hoc ab eterno fuerat in deo, ergo deus ab eterno potuit facere mundum et sciuit, et uoluit121, ergo ab eterno fecit illum122.
-
5. Item uidetur per Augustinum probari. Dicit enim et uerum est, quod deus quia bonus est, sumus 123. Sed ab eterno bonus est124, ergo ab eterno sumus.
-
6. Item125 summe bonitatis est semper effluere126. Sed ab eterno fuit summa bonitas, ergo ab eterno fluxit. Sed eius effluxio nichil127 aliud est quam mundi et eorum, que in mundo sunt128, creatio.
-
7. Ergo creatio129 mundi ab eterno est, quod non potest esse. Cum enim mundus creatura sit, de necessitate habet principium130 et ita131 ab eterno non est, quod concedimus.
-
8. Dicimus ergо ad primum, quod proposicio Aristotelis tantum tenet in naturalis, ubi est tantum naturalis ordo principii et principiati et non uoluntarius.
-
9. Ad secundum dicimus, quod causa uoluntaria dilatoria est. Preelegit enim, quod et quando res132 faciat133, unde non sequitur in creaturis: uult hoc facere, ergo facit. Concedimus ergo, quod deus ab eterno uoluit mundum facere. Non tamen uoluit illum facere ab eterno, sed tunc134, quando fecit, unde est ibi fallacia composicionis et diuisionis135.
-
10. Ad ultimum dicimus, quod summe bonitatis triplex est effluxio136, scilicet per generationem, per spirationem, per creationem. Due prime sunt naturales, tercia uoluntaria. Due prime fuerunt137 ab eterno et in138 illis maxime apparet summa bonitas et summa perfectio. Tercia cepit esse cum tempore nec in illo apparuit summe bonitatis immensitas. Totus enim | 46ra | mundus est quasi quedam parua stilla bonitatis dei et mirabilius est139, quomodo140 potuit tam paruum facere, quam quod de nichilo fecit.
-
11. Quod autem Plato et Epicurus ponunt eternam materiam, de qua deus, cum uellet, posset operari, decepti fuerunt, suspicantes ad modum hominis deum non posse de nichilo141 operari, quod si esset, omnipotens non esset.
-
12. Manicheus142 autem hiis abutitur rationibus ad probandum errorem suum.
-
13. Cuius causa est inuariabilis, ipsum est inuariabilis143. Sed bonus144 est inuariabilis, ergo non est causa uariabilium siue uisibilium.
-
14. Item nichil est causa constructiua et destructiua eiusdem145. Sed bonus deus est causa constructiua malorum hominum, ergo non est causa destructiua eorumdem.
-
15. Item сontrariorum contraria sunt principia146. Sed bonus deus est principium bonorum, ergo non est principium malorum et aliquid est principium malorum. Ergo deus malus, qui est summe malus et ideo principium malorum, sicut deus bonus est summe bonus et ideo principium bonorum.
-
16. Sed ad hoc debet dici147, quod prima proposicio Manichei non ualet, nisi in causis coniunctis suis effectibus. Immo necesse est, quod omne uariabile sit ab inuariabili, sicut motus ab immobili et multitudo148 ab unitate.
-
17. Secunda proposicio est falsa in uoluntariis, ut patet in fabro, qui sepe destruit, quod fecerat.
-
18. Tercia simpliciter falsa est, ut patet in primis contrariis149, que fuerunt ab eodem. Aliter processus esset in150 infinitum aut tot essent principia, quot sunt contraria, quod etiam contra ipsos est, qui non ponunt, nisi duo151 principia, scilicet unum bonorum summe bonum et aliud malorum summe malum.
-
19. 152Esse creatorem, per hoc, quod dicit creauit , initium, per hoc, quod dicit in principio , uisibilium, per terram autem; inuisibilium153154, per celum . 155In uno prin-cipio , id est in initio temporis uel in filio156, esse factum157, id est creatum, 158sine principio, id est initio.
-
20. Quod autem sit unum principium tantum omnium rerum, probatur sic159.
-
21. Quod per superhabundaciam dicitur uni soli conuenit, ergo unicum est summe bonum, ergo unicum est principium rerum.
-
22. Preterea, si essent plura160 summe bona, ergo essent diffirencia, ergo aliquid haberet unum, quod non reliquum. Sed summe bonum non habet in se nisi bonum, ergo aliquid bonum haberet unum, quod non reliquum, ergo illud non esset summe bonum, cum alio bono careret.
-
23. Sed notandum, quod cum dicitur in principio creauit deus celum et cetera161, Manichei dicunt, quod Moyses loquitur de deo malo162, qui fecit omnia uisibilia secundum eos.
-
24. Sed ipsi bene concedunt, quod deus bonus est summe bonum et tale, quo163 melius excogitari non potest164.
-
25. Sed secundum eos sunt plura principia: unum bonorum, aliud malorum, quia duo contraria non possunt habere unum principium, ut dicunt.
-
26. Sed contra eos sic obicitur.
-
27. Posse165 cohibere malum est bonum166, hec proposicio per se nota est. Sed deus bonus aut habet illud bonum, aut non. Si non, ergo aliquo167 bono caret, ergo non est summe bonum nec tale, quo melius excogitari non potest.
-
28. Item posse cohibere malum168 est posse bonum. Sed deus bonus non potest illud, ergo non est omnipotens. Si dicas, quod deus bonus potest cohibere malum, ergo potest cohibere deum ma | 46rb | lum, ne faciat malum. Ergo deus malus ex se et per se non potest operari malum, quia169, si ex se et per se haberet illam potenciam, non posset impediri, sicut deus bonus non potest impediri ab operatione boni, ergo non est summe malus.
-
29. 170Tria171172, id est principia sine initio: exemplar, id est ydeas; materiam, id est yle173; 174quasi175 artificem, qui operatur ex preiacenti materia; uocaturque176 factor177, homo uel angelus. 178Et creare sicut facere, cum dicitur deus facit hanc rem , hoc uerbum facit predicat diuinam essenciam, ut causam, et connotat179 in creatura habitudinem creature ad factorem siue creatorem, scilicet habitudinem180 effectus ad causam, que uoluntarie operator. Sed dictum de creatura significat actionem, que est accidentalis proprietas, hoc uerbum creat pretar hoc remouet materiam. Uerumtamen181 et cetera182, idem est deo esse et183 uelle, creare et184 facere185, sed deus est ab eterno et uult ab eterno, ergo facit et creat ab eterno186.
-
30. Solutio187, quo ad principale significatum idem sunt. Sed creat et facit connotant aliquid188 creatum et temporale ratione, cuius non sunt idem, unde cum
-
31. Operatorium, id est dictum, qui operatur. Ex hiis Aristoteles194 appellat principia, que sunt de re, ut materia et forma, que duo pro uno principio reputat, quod non sequitur; et tercium operatorium dictum non est intelligendum tercium principium, quia sic non consonat littera. Sed tercium a predictis duobus, que sumit pro uno principio et illud tercium pro secundo principio, et sic ponit duo esse principia. Et potest hoc dictio dictum uel adiectiue accipi, uel substantiue addicendo quasi dictione operatorium : dixit enim et facta sunt.
-
32. 195Tradens, per Moysen196, et ante tempora significat197, quando198 enim tempora crearet, si prius non esset199, 200exstitisse, scilicet deum.
malum siue deum tenebrarum, siue deum Ueteris Testamenti, hunc dicebant tantum esse principium rerum corporalium109.110
dicitur
deus creat
, hoc189 est sensus: deus est, ex cuius uoluntate hoc consistit, quid enim est aliud, ut ait Augustinus:
deo auctore factum est, nisi deo
190
uolente, nec tamen uelle est facere
191. Licet figuratiue dicatur ob hoc, scilicet quia uoluntatem eius necessario sequitur effectus, sicut misericordia dei et iusticia idem sunt, non tamen idem est punire et parcere,
192agitatione,
id est
HUGH OF SAINT-CHER
THE WORK. BOOK II. DISTINCTION I. THE FIRST PART
The second book begins.
create the world, he knew and desired that from eternity, so he created it from eternity.
that reason the beginning of evil as the good God is the highest good and for that reason the beginning of good.
(called) or as a noun (word) by adding an operating word: for he said (dixit) and things were made.
Список литературы Between eternity and divine dualism: Hugh of Saint-Cher’s Opus II, pars I
- Albertus Magnus (1894) Super II Sententiarum, ed. E. Borgnet. Vives (Op. 27).
- Alexander de Hales (1952) Glossa in quatuor libros sententiarum Petri Lombardi. In librum secundum, eds. Quaracchi Friars. Collegium S. Bonaventurae.
- Ambrosius (1845) Opera omnia, ed. J.-P. Migne. Garnier (PL, 14).
- Angotti, C. (2012) “Apprendre À Lire les Sentences de Pierre Lombard À L’Université de Paris (XIIIe–XIVe Siècles),” Revue de Synthèse 133, 195–213.
- Anonyme (1973) Livre des deux principes, éd. et trad. par C. Thouzellier. Éditions du Cerf.
- Aristoteles (1951) Physica, ed. W.D. Ross. Oxford University Press.
- Aristoteles (1957) Aristotelis Metaphysica, ed. W. Jaeger. Clarendon Press.
- Aristoteles (1975) De sophisticis elenchis. Translatio Boethii, Fragmenta Translationis Iacobi, et Recensio Guillelmi de Moerbeke, ed. B.G. Dod. Brill-Desclée de Brouwer (Aristoteles Latinus 6.1–3).
- Aristoteles (1990) Physica: Translatio Vetus, eds. F. Bossier, J. Brams. Brepols Publishers (Aristoteles Latinus 7.1).
- Aristoteles (1997) De Generatione Et Corruptione: Translatio Vetus, ed. J. Judycka. Brill (Aristoteles Latinus 9.1).
- Assisi, Fondo Antico presso la Biblioteca del Sacro Convento, MS 130.
- Assisi, Fondo Antico presso la Biblioteca del Sacro Convento, MS 131.
- Aurelius Augustinus (1970) De diversis quaestionibus octoginta tribus, ed. A. Mutzenbecher. Turnhout.
- Aurelius Augustinus (1995) De doctrina Christiana, ed. R.P.H. Green. Clarendon Press.
- Avencebrolis (1892) Fons Vitae, ex Arabico in Latinum Translatus ab Johanne Hispano et Dominico Gundissalino, ed. C. Baeumker. Aschendorff.
- Avicenna (1977) Liber de philosophia prima sive scientia divina. Volumes 1–4, eds. S. van Riet, G.Verbeke. Peeters Publishers.
- Barichard, L.-H. (2012) Problème du mal dans la Summa de bono de Philippe le Chancelier, MA thesis. Université de Montréal.
- Basile de Césarée (1950) Homélies sur l'Hexaéméron: Texte grec, introduction et traduction de S. Giet. Éditions du Cerf.
- Bataillon, L.-J. (2004) “L’influence d’Hugues de Saint-Cher,” in: L.-J. Bataillon, G. Dahan, P.-M. Gy, eds. Hugues de Saint-Cher († 1263), bibliste et théologien. Brepols, Turnhout, 497–502.
- Beda Venerabilis (1862) In pentateuhum commentarii. Expositio in primum librum Mosis, ed. J.-P. Migne. Garnier (PL, 91).
- Bériou, N. (2004) “Federico Visconti, archevêque de Pise, disciple de Hugues de Saint-Cher,” in: L.-J. Bataillon, G. Dahan, P.-M. Gy, eds. Hugues de Saint-Cher († 1263), bibliste et théologien. Brepols, Turnhout, 253–269.
- Bianchi, L.M. (1984) L'errore di Aristotele. La polemica contro l'eternità del mondo nel XIII seculo. La Nuova Italia.
- Bianchi, L.M. (2005) “Aristotle as a captive bride: notes on Gregory IX’s attitude toward Aristotelianism,” in: L. Honnefelder, R. Wood, M. Dreyer, M.-A. Aris, eds. Albertus Magnus und die Anfänge der Aristoteles-Rezeption im lateinischen Mittelalter. Von Richardus Rufus bis zu Franciscus de Mayronis, 777–794.
- Bianchi, L.M. (2013) “Couper, distinguer, compléter : trois stratégies de lecture d’Aristote à la Faculté des arts,” in: J. Verger, O. Weijers, eds. Les débuts de l’enseignement universitaire à Paris (1200–1245 environ). Brepols, Turnhout, 133–152.
- Bieniak, M. (2007) “L'innascibilitas du Père dans le commentaire d'Hugues de Saint-Cher sur les Sentences de Pierre Lombard. Édition du texte (In Sent. I, dist. 28),” Archives d'histoire doctrinale et littéraire du Moyen Âge 74, 161–171.
- Bieniak, M. (2009) “The Sentences Commentary Of Hugh Of St.-Cher,” in: P.W. Rosemann, ed. Mediaeval Commentaries on the Sentences of Peter Lombard. Volume 2. Brill, Leiden, 111–147.
- Bieniak, M. (2010) The Soul-Body Problem at Paris, ca. 1200–1250. Hugh of St-Cher and His Contemporaries. Leuven University Press.
- Bieniak M. (2013) “Contents of Hugh of St.-Cher's Commentary on the Sentences, Books I–II,” Przegląd Tomistyczny 19, 9–91.
- Biller, P. (1999) “Northern Cathars and Higher Learning,” Studies in Church History Subsidia 11, 25–53.
- Bonaventura (1938) Liber II Sententiarum, ed. Quaracchi Friars. Collegium S. Bonaventurae (T. II).
- Bougerol, J.G. (1983) “Autour de 'La naissance du Purgatoire',” Archives d'histoire doctrinale et littéraire du Moyen Âge 50, 7–59.
- Boureau, A. (2007) L'Empire du livre: Pour une histoire du savoir scolastique (1200–1380). Les Belles Lettres.
- Boureau, A. (2014a) “Une nature préservée de la transgression humaine des normes. Physique des éléments et géologie du monde dans l'exégèse et la théologie du XIIIe siècle,” Micrologus 58, 55–94.
- Boureau, A. (2014b) Le désir dicté: Histoire du voeu religieux dans l'Occident médiéval. Les Belles Lettres.
- Brugge, Hoofdbibliotheek Biekorf Brugge, MS 178.
- Città del Vaticano, Biblioteca Apostolica Vaticana, MS Vat. lat. 1098.
- Città del Vaticano, Biblioteca Apostolica Vaticana, MS Vat. lat. 2435.
- Città del Vaticano, Biblioteca Apostolica Vaticana, MS Vat. lat. 5982.
- Città del Vaticano, Biblioteca Apostolica Vaticana, MS Vat. lat. 691.
- Città del Vaticano, Biblioteca Apostolica Vaticana, MS Vat. lat. 729.
- Città del Vaticano, Biblioteca Apostolica Vaticana, MS Vat. lat. 7669.
- Clark, M. J. (2005) “Peter Comestor and Peter Lombard: Brothers in Deed,” Traditio 60, 85–142.
- Colish, M.L. (1994) Peter Lombard. Brill.
- Dales, R.C. (1987) “Early Latin Discussions of the Eternity of the World in the Thirteenth Century,” Traditio 43, 171–197.
- Dales, R.C. (1989) Medieval Discussions of the Eternity of the World. Brill.
- Dionysiaca (1937) Recueil donnant l'ensemble des traductions latines des ouvrages attribués au Denys de l'Aréopage ... Tome premier, ed. P. Chevallier. Desclée de Brouwer.
- Dronke, P. (1988) “Thierry of Chartres,” in: P. Dronke, ed. A History of Twelfth Century Western Philosophy. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 358–385.
- Ehrle, F. (1925) L'agostinismo e l'aristotelismo nella scolastica del sec. XIII, vol. III. Tipografia Vaticana.
- Faes de Mottoni, B. (2004) “Les manuscrits du commentaire des Sentences de Hugues de Saint-Cher,” in: L.-J. Bataillon, G. Dahan, P.-M. Gy, eds. Hugues de Saint-Cher (†1263), bibliste et théologien. Brepols, Turnhout, 273–298.
- Friedman, R.L. (2002) “The Sentences Commentary, 1250–1320. General Trends, The Impact
- of the Religious Orders, and the Test Case of Predestination,” in: G.R. Evans,
- ed. Mediaeval Commentaries on the Sentences of Peter Lombard. Volume 1. Brill, Leiden,
- Boston, Köln, 41–128.
- Gauthier, R.A. (1982) “Notes sur les débuts (1225–1240) du premier 'averroïsme',” Revue des Sciences philosophiques et théologiques 66(3), 321–374.
- Gorochov, N. (2012) Naissance de l’université. Les écoles de Paris, d’Innocent III à Thomas d’Aquin. v. 1200 – v. 1245. Honoré Champion.
- Gorochov, N. (2021) “Odo Rigaldus at the University of Paris (c.1220–48),” in: L. Schumacher, ed. The Legacy of Early Franciscan Thought. De Gruyter, Berlin, Boston, 151–168.
- Grabmann, M. (1941) I Divieti ecclesiastici di Aristotelesotto Innocenzo III e Gregorio IX. Pontificia Università Gregoriana.
- Gregorius Nyssenus (2009) Opera exegetica In Genesim, pars I, ed. by H.R. Drobner. Brill.
- Grice, D. (2019) Church, Society and University: The Paris Condemnation of 1241/4. Routledge.
- Guillermus Altissiodorensis (1982) Magistri Guillelmi Altissiodorensis Summa aurea, ed. J. Ribaillier. Collegium S. Bonaventurae (Liber II–I).
- Hamesse, J. (1974) Les Auctoritates Aristotelis. Un florilège médiéval. Étude historique et edition critique. Louvain publications universitaires.
- Ioannes Philoponus (1897) De opificio mundi libri VII, ed. G. Reichardt. Bibliotheca Teubneriana.
- Landgraf, A.M. (1952). Der Sentenzenkommentar des Kardinals Stephan Langton. Aschendorff Verlag. Leipzig, Universitätsbibliothek Leipzig, MS 1401.
- Lizzini, O. (2013) “Flusso, preparazione appropriata e inchoatio formae: brevi osservazioni su Avicenna e Alberto Magno,” in: M. Lenzi, C.A. Musatti, L. Valente, eds. Medioevo e filosofia : per Alfonso Maierù. Viella, Roma, 129–150.
- Maier, A. (1968) Zwei Grundprobleme der scholastischen Naturphilosophie: Das Problem der intensiven Grösse, die Impetustheorie. Edizioni di storia e letteratura.
- Moneta Cremonensis (1743) Adversus Catharos et Valdenses Libri quinque, ed. T.A. Ricchinius. Oxford, Balliol College, MS 62.
- Paravicini Bagliani, A. (1972) Cardinali di curia e “familiae” cardinalizie dal 1227 al 1254. Editrice Antenore.
- Paris, Bibliothèque nationale de France, MS lat. 10728.
- Paris, Bibliothèque nationale de France, MS lat. 14423.
- Paris, Bibliothèque nationale de France, MS lat. 14526.
- Paris, Bibliothèque nationale de France, MS lat. 15652.
- Paris, Bibliothèque nationale de France, MS lat. 16412.
- Paris, Bibliothèque nationale de France, MS lat. 3073.
- Petrus Lombardus (1971) Petri Lombardi Sententiae in IV Libris distinctae, ed. by ed. Quaracchi Friars. Collegium S. Bonaventurae (T. IVb, v. I, p. II).
- Plato (1902) Timaeus, ed. J. Burned. Oxford University Press (Platonis Opera. Tomus IV. Tetralogia VIII).
- Plato (1962) Timaeus a Caldio translatus commentarioque instructus, ed. by J.H. Waszink. The Warburg Institute; Brill.
- Polloni, N. (2015) Ontologie divergenti: uno studio sul sincretismo metafisico di Gundisalvi. PhD Thesis. Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona.
- Porro, P. (1996) Forme e modelli di durata nel pensiero medievale. L’aevum, il tempo discreto, la categoria “quando”. Leuven University Press.
- Rosemann, P.W. (2004) Peter Lombard. Oxford University Press.
- Russell, J.B. (1984) Lucifer, the Devil in the Middle Ages. Cornell University Press.
- Saccenti, R. (2010) “Quidam dicunt quod aqua sive ablutio, quidam quod character: Discussioni sulla natura del battesimo fra la metà del XII e i primi decenni del XIII secolo,” Cristianesimo nella storia 31(2), 387–417.
- Saccenti, R. (2013) Conservare la retta volontà. L'atto morale nelle dottrine di Filippo il Cancelliere e Ugo di Saint-Cher (1225–1235). Il Mulino. Saint-Omer, Bibliothèque de l'Agglomération de Saint Omer, MS 595.
- Smith, L. (2010) “Hugh of St Cher and Medieval Collaboration,” in: F.T. Harkins, ed. Transforming Relations: Essays on Jews and Christians throughout History in Honor of Michael A. Signer. University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame, 241–264.
- Stroumsa, G.G. (1992) “Anti-Cathar Polemics and the Liber de duobus principiis,” in: B. Lewis, F. Niewöhner, eds. Religionsgespräche im Mittelalter. Harrassowitz, Wiesbaden, 169–183.
- Thomas de Aquino (1856) Scriptum super Sententiis, ed. Commissio Leonina. Ex Typographia Polyglotta S. C. de Propaganda Fide.
- Torrell, J.-P. (1974) Théorie de la prophétie et philosophie de la connaissance aux environs de 1230. La contribution d'Hugues de Saint-Cher (ms Douai 434, Quest. 481). Spicilegium Sacrum Lovaniense.
- Van der Lugt, M. (2004) Le ver, le démon et la vierge: Les théories médiévales de la generation extraordinaire. Une étude sur les rapports entre théologie, philosophie naturelle et médecine. Les Belles Lettres.
- Van Steenberghen, F. (1966) La philosophie au XIIIe siècle. Publications Universitaires, Béatrice-Nauwelaerts.
- Wicki, N. (2005) Die Philosophie Philipps des Kanzlers: ein philosophierender Theologe des frühen 13. Jahrhunderts. Academic Press.
- Young, S.E. (2014) Scholarly Community at the Early University of Paris: Theologians, Education and Society, 1215–1248. Cambridge University Press.